Perception and Its Objects
https://doi.org/10.1007/S11098-006-9051-2…
24 pages
1 file
Sign up for access to the world's latest research
Abstract
AI
AI
The paper seeks to rehabilitate the early modern empiricist perspective on perception, arguing for an 'Object View' (OV) where the core subjective character of perceptual experience is constituted by the mind-independent physical objects presented in that experience, even in cases of illusion. It critiques the current orthodox 'Content View' (CV), indicating its difficulties in addressing visual illusions, and emphasizing the significance of objects as central to understanding perceptual experience.
FAQs
AI
What is the difference between the Object View and the Content View in perception?add
The paper reveals that the Object View insists on mind-independent physical objects as direct perceptual objects, while the Content View argues for perceptual experience being fundamentally representational.
How does the Object View account for visual illusions like the Müller-Lyer illusion?add
The Object View explains that in cases like the Müller-Lyer illusion, the direct object presented is mind-independent but appears different due to visually relevant similarities with paradigm instances.
What challenges does (CV) face in explaining perceptual experiences involving illusion?add
The study demonstrates that (CV) struggles to reconcile the notion of false representation in perception with the idea that physical objects are directly experienced despite illusions.
What is the significance of visually relevant similarities in perceptual experience according to (OV)?add
(OV) posits that visually relevant similarities help explain how mind-independent objects can be perceived in various ways, directly influencing the subjective character of experience.
How does the paper characterize hallucinations in relation to the Object View?add
Hallucinations are described as experiences lacking mind-independent direct objects, requiring qualitative descriptions rather than reliance on perceptual content to characterize them.
Related papers
1 We focus on the visual case, leaving it to the reader to consider how the discussion generalizes to other modalities. 2 concerned how the transition from introspective beliefs to external--world beliefs could be rational. 2 In this entry, we assume without argument these positions are mistaken. We begin from the assumption that experiences (such as the one you have when you see the mustard) can justify external world beliefs about the things you see, such as beliefs that the mustard jar is in the fridge, and that the justification experience provides does not have to rely on justification for introspective beliefs. From now on, we often let it remain implicit that we are talking about external world beliefs, when we talk about the kind of beliefs that experiences justify. 3 Our main question is this: what features of experiences explain how they justify external world beliefs? The grammar of the question might suggest that experiences suffice all by themselves to provide justification for external world beliefs. But don't read this into the grammar of the phrase "experiences justify beliefs". We can distinguish between the claim that an experience can justify a belief that P, and the claim that an experience can justify a belief that P without help from other features it only contingently has. We clarify our question further in Part I, where we explain why we have chosen this point of departure, and highlight a range of theses about the role of experience in providing different types of justification. In Parts II and III, we consider the role of features of experience falling into two broad categories: constitutive features of experience, including its phenomenal character, its contents, its status as attentive or inattentive (sections 3--7); and causal features of experience such as its reliability, and the impact of other mental states on its formation (sections 8--10). Along the way, we discuss the relationships between visual experience and seeing (sections 1 and 8), and we contrast perceptual justification and perceptual knowledge (section 9).
The Contents of Perceptual Experience: A Kantian Perspective, 2014
When I observe a scene around me, I perceive a number of objects: I can see my desk with a pile of books and papers on it (in slight disarray), some writing implements and a notebook; I can hear a car passing the nearby road and friends chatting outside my window; I can sense the smell of freshly baked bread and feel the smoothness of my cat's fur. What are the objects of my perception-in general? Surely, I can think about these objects, as well as imagine them. But there must be something in perception that makes it different from other mental states, acts or processes, such as thinking or imagining. For example, smelling a rose is different from merely thinking about a rose. When you smell a rose, you have certain sensations that you would not have if you were merely thinking about it. Moreover, you would not know what the scent of rose is like, you would not be able to recognize it as coming from your garden, and to tell it apart from the scent of lilacs that grow next to roses, if you did not have a perceptual experience of a rose. Accordingly, philosophers have claimed that what distinguishes perception from other kinds of mental states, acts, or processes, is its content. Since the objects that can be perceived can also be thought about or imagined, perceptual content is a special way or mode in which objects can be given, or presented, to us in experience or, more broadly, cognition. Let us call this view the content view (CV).23 On the CV, cognitive access to objects would be regarded as mediated, rather than direct. The role of the intermediary would be played by representational content. This view is deeply rooted in the history of philosophy, for example in the debates between direct and indirect realists, such as Thomas Reid, on the one hand, and John Locke, on the other.24 The latter, also known as representationists, would claim that "ideas," which would be characterized as mind-dependent, or existing "in" the mind, mediate access to all kinds of objects. The standard objection raised against the CV states that it encourages skepticism about the properties of the objects outside the 23 For a discussion and critique of the view, see: B.
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 2019
This paper develops a form of transcendental na€ ıve realism. According to na€ ıve realism, veridical perceptual experiences are essentially relational. According to transcendental na€ ıve realism, the na€ ıve realist theory of perception is not just one theory of perception amongst others, to be established as an inference to the best explanation and assessed on the basis of a cost-benefit analysis that weighs performance along a number of different dimensions: for instance, fidelity to appearances, simplicity, systematicity, fit with scientific theories, and so on. Rather, na€ ıve realism enjoys a special status in debates in the philosophy of perception because it represents part of the transcendental project of explaining how it is possible that perceptual experience has the distinctive characteristics it does. One of the potentially most interesting prospects of adopting a transcendental attitude towards na€ ıve realism is that it promises to make the na€ ıve realist theory of perception, in some sense, immune to falsification. This paper develops a modest form of transcendental na€ ıve realism modelled loosely on the account of the reactive attitudes provided by Strawson in 'Freedom and Resentment', and suggests one way of understanding the claim that na€ ıve realism is immune to falsification. 1. Transcendental Na€ ıve Realism According to the version of the na€ ıve realist theory of perception that I will take as representative, veridical perceptual experiences are essentially relational: veridical perceptual experiences are constituted at least in part by the mind-independent objects and properties in our environment that they are experiences of. Because on this view veridical perceptual experiences are essentially relational, a particular perceptual experience could not have occurred if the subject had not been perceptually related to precisely those elements of their environment. 1 In this respect, na€ ıve realist theories of perception differ from common kind theories of perception, like sense-datum or representationalist theories, which allow that how things are with the subject is constitutively independent, at least on a particular occasion, of how things are in their environment. According to common kind theories, it is possible for the subject to have fundamentally the same kind of experience whether or not the environment This is an open access article under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits use, distribution and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Erkenntnis, https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00328-y, 2020
Entities that are, in ordinary perceptual situations, veridically presented as objects can be called 'perceptual objects'. In the philosophical literature, one can find various approaches to the crucial features that distinguish the class of perceptual objects. While these positions differ in many respects, they share an important general feature: they all characterize perceptual objects as largely subject-independent. More specifically, they do not attribute a significant constitutive role to the perceptual relation connecting a fragment of the environment with a perceiving subject. Fragments of the environment are perceptual objects no matter whether they stand in a perceptual relation to any subject, mainly by virtue of having a certain physical structure. I question this common assumption, relying on Green's (2019) definition of perceptual objects, arguing that a proper theory of perceptual objects should accommodate the constitutive role of perceptual relations. This is because there exist fragments of the environment that are perceptual objects only when they stand in a perceptual relation to a subject.
Perceptual Experience, 2006
There seems to be a large gulf between percepts and concepts. In particular, concepts seem to be capable of representing things that percepts cannot. We can conceive of things that would be impossible to perceive. (The converse may also seem true, but I will leave that to one side.) In one respect, this is trivially right. We can conceive of things that we cannot encounter, such as unicorns. We cannot literally perceive unicorns, even if we occasionally ''see'' them in our dreams and hallucinations. To avoid triviality, I want to focus on things that we can actually encounter. We perceive poodles, perfumes, pinpricks, and pounding drums. These are concrete things; they are closely wedded to appearances. But we also encounter things that are abstract. We encounter uncles and instances of injustice. These things have no characteristic looks. Percepts, it is said, cannot represent abstract things. Call this claim the Imperceptability Thesis. I think the Imperceptibility Thesis is false. Perception is not restricted to the concrete. We can perceive abstract entities. This may sound like an obvious claim. We often use perceptual terms widely to say things such as: ''I perceive a lack of agreement'' or ''I see where you are going with that argument.'' But, by most accounts, these uses of perceptual terms are either metaphorical or, at any rate, different from the use of perceptual terms in cases that more directly involve the sense modalities: ''I perceive distant rumbling''; ''I see a red light over there.'' The abstract cases are interpreted as involving the sense modalities, if only indirectly. The presumption is that we must first pick up something with our senses and then judge that there is, say, a lack of agreement. Moreover, the abstract cases are presumed to require a level of mental representation that is not perceptual in format. I want to deny all of this. Perceiving abstracta can be just like perceiving concreta. Those willing to abandon the Imperceptibility Thesis might dig in their heels elsewhere. If there is no semantic gulf between percepts and concepts, there I am deeply indebted to two anonymous referees and, especially, Tamar Gendler. This paper benefited tremendously from their detailed comments and excellent advice.
European Journal of Philosophy, 1997
A commonly held view about the relation between consciousness and reference can be summarised, roughly, as follows. Demonstrative reference to objects we perceive is object-dependent: which objects our experience-based thoughts refer to depends on which objects in our immediate environment are, in fact, the cause of our experiences. How things are from within the perspective of consciousness, on the other hand, is object-independent. Experiences as of qualitatively indistinguishable objects are the same from within the perspective of consciousness, irrespective of the identity of the particular object, if any, that is the cause of the experience. In slogan form the claims are: reference is object-dependent and consciousness is object-independent. 1 The basic argument for object-dependence of demonstrative reference is Strawson's. 2 The possibility of massive reduplication of any one section of the universe onto another means that descriptions in purely general terms cannot fix the reference of any singular term. Reference to particular spatio-temporal objects must be anchored by demonstrative ways of thinking which are such that we can determine their referents by appealing to subjects' de facto perceptual relations with objects in their environment. The second claim, that how things are from the perspective of consciousness is object-independent, says that such object-dependence in reference goes beyond what is available from within the perspective of consciousness. From within that perceptive all that is given are general properties. If two objects are qualitatively indistinguishable there can be no difference for the subject in how things are from within the perspective of consciousness. The fact of numerical distinctness is a fact that is extrinsic to the delineation of how things are from within consciousness. 3 Though commonly held, this is a wholly unacceptable combination of claims. Consciousness is what makes knowledge possible. The realm of consciousness is the realm of how things are for the subject, from her perspective. If it were the case that consciousness is object-independent, and reference determination object-dependent, the conclusion would have to be that we cannot have knowledge of which objects our experience-based singular thoughts concern. A brazen response to this charge, which will not be my concern in this paper, is to claim that the insistence on a connection between consciousness and knowledge and reference is a manifestation of lingering Cartesian tendencies that must
Philosophical Studies, 2006
John Campbell argues that visual attention to objects is the means by which we can refer to objects, and that this is so because conscious visual attention enables us to retrieve information about a location. It is argued here that while Campbell is right to think that we visually attend to objects, he does not give us sufficient ground for thinking that consciousness is involved, and is wrong to assign an intermediary role to location. Campbell's view on sortals is also queried, as is his espousal of the so-called Referential View of Experience. 1. OBJECT-PERCEPTION, ATTENTION, AND LOCATION Visual consciousness presents us with features or qualities À blue, shiny, round, etc. À arranged in some kind of map (see Clark, 2000 for a sophisticated version of this thesis). It is a standard assumption in philosophy that our awareness of objects is constructed out of our awareness of such feature
King’s Research Portal
DOI:
10.1007/s11098−006−9051−2
Document Version
Preprint - the version submitted for publication
Link to publication record in King’s Research Portal
Citation for published version (APA):
Brewer, B. (2007). Perception and its objects. PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES, 132(1), 87-97. 10.1007/s11098-006-9051-2
Page numbers
When referring to this paper, please check the page numbers in the published version and cite these.
General rights
Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights.
- Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research.
- You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain
- You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal?
Take down policy
If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact librarypure@kcl.ac.uk providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim.
Open Access document downloaded from King’s Research Portal https://kclpure.kcl.ac.uk/portal
Citation to published version:
[Brewer, B. (2007). Perception and its objects. PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES, 132(1), 87-97, doi: 10.1007/s11098-006-9051-2]
The published version is available at:
DOI: [10.1007/s11098-006-9051-2]
This version: [Pre-Print]
URL identifying the publication in the King’s Portal:
[https://kclpure.kcl.ac.uk/portal/en/publications/perception-and-its-objects(83554add-964e-47e2-ad39-f92579c74bae).html]
The copyright in the published version resides with the publisher.
When referring to this paper, please check the page numbers in the published version and cite these.
General rights
Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in King’s Research Portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications in King’s Research Portal that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights.
- Users may download and print one copy of any publication from King’s Research Portal for the purpose of private study or research.
- You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain
- You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the King’s Research Portal
Take down policy
If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact librarypure@kcl.ac.uk providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim.
PERCEPTION AND ITS OBJECTS
BILL BREWER
Here is an influential inconsistent triad of claims concerning the nature of perceptual experience and its objects.
(1) Physical objects are mind-independent.
(2) Physical objects are the direct objects of perception.
(3) The direct objects of perception are mind-dependent.
Physical objects are such things as stones, tables, trees, people and other animals: the persisting macroscopic constituents of the world we live in. For the entities of a given kind to be mind-independent is for them to exist, and be intrinsically as they are, independently of anyone’s thought or experience of them. Otherwise they are minddependent in some way.
According to the early modern empiricists, especially Locke (1975) and Berkeley (1975a, 1975b), the core subjective character of a perceptual experience is to be given simply by citing the object presented in that experience. In line with that approach, the direct objects of perception are those objects, if any, which constitute its core subjective character, which identify any given perceptual experience as the specific core modification of consciousness which it is. There may be experiences which cannot be characterized in
this way: their subjective character has to be given otherwise than by reference to any particular such object; and, although such experiences may be related in various ways to objects of various other kinds, none of these is their direct object in my technical sense.
(1) expresses a commonsense commitment to what might be called physical realism. I take (2) to be the most natural expression of the equally commonsense idea that physical objects are the objects which are presented to us in perception, whose nature is made evident to us by the subjective character of our perceptual experience. We shall see, though, that there is an alternative strategy for retaining the idea that physical objects are the very things which are presented to us in perception, which we see, feel, hear, and so on, without regarding these as direct objects in my sense. Still, the conjunction of (1) and (2) provides the most natural formulation, at least, of empirical realism, the intuitive thesis that the objects which are presented to us in perception, such as stones, tables, trees, people and other animals, nevertheless exist, and are intrinsically as they are, quite independently of our perception of them, and, indeed, of anyone’s thought or experience of them.
(3) is the conclusion of a philosophical argument: the argument from illusion. Very crudely, in cases of illusion, the direct object of perception has a property which no candidate mind-independent object has, and must therefore be mind-dependent; then, since every perceptual experience is subjectively identical to one in a possible case of illusion, the same goes across the board. The direct objects of any perception are always mind-dependent. This line of argument may be made precise in a number of importantly
different ways. I think that Paul Snowdon is right to distinguish two phases in each of them (1992). The first is intended to establish that the direct object of an illusion is minddependent. The second is supposed to generalize this result to all perceptual experience, including that involved in veridical perception. There are serious problems with any version of phase two which I know. It is sufficient for my purposes here, though, to elaborate phase one as follows.
A visual illusion may be characterized as an experience in which a physical object, o, looks E, although o is not actually F. 1 According to the early modern empiricist insight, the way to account for the fact that something looks F in an experience is to construe that experience as the presentation to the subject of a direct object, which constitutes the core subjective character of the experience, and which must, therefore, supposedly, actually be
F. In cases of illusion, then, this direct object is distinct from the physical object o which is not F.
On Locke’s materialist view, indirect realism, the direct object of an illusion is a minddependent entity, which is F, which nevertheless sufficiently resembles a non- F, mindindependent object, o, for the latter to be the physical object which illusorily looks F. 2On
1 I concentrate throughout on the case of vision. I believe that much of what I say applies equally to the other modalities, although I do not address this here. There are plausible counterexamples to the sufficiency of this characterization of visual illusion; but it is adequate for present purposes. My forthcoming ‘How to Account for Illusion’, and Perception and its Objects, contain further discussion.
2 Things are of course more complicated in case of secondary qualities, according to Locke. For, in one sense, all secondary quality perception is illusory: nothing in the mind-independent physical world is red, in the basic sense in which mind-dependent ideas are red. Still, in having such an idea before the mind, a physical thing may be said ↩︎
the most straightforward version of Berkeley’s mentalism, on the other hand, the direct object of an illusion is a mind-dependent entity, which is a part of an equally minddependent composite physical object o.O is not F, very roughly, because most of its parts are not F, and it does not behave, in general, in ways characteristic of F 's: in particular we cannot use it as we can paradigm F 's. Nevertheless, it looks F, on this occasion, because the part presented in the relevant illusory experience is F. 3 Both approaches are widely regarded as unsatisfactory today, absolutely rightly in my view. 4
According to current orthodoxy, the mistake goes right back to the idea that perceptual experience has its core subjective character given simply by citing its direct object, which must apparently therefore be F in a case of illusion, and hence must be distinct from the physical object, o, which illusorily looks F although it is not. The subjective character of perceptual experience is to be given instead by its representational content: how it represents things as being in the physical world around the subject. In an illusion, perception has the false representational content that o is F. In general, o looks F iff o is
to look red*, that is, either disposed to produce red ideas in normal observers in normal conditions, or microscopically constituted in whichever way actually grounds that disposition. Some, but not all, such perceptions may then be illusory in a derived sense, in which something looks red* which is not. None of these details are relevant for present purposes.
3 See Stoneham (2002) for a compelling presentation of this account of Berkeley. Note, as with Locke’s account of the secondary qualities, predicates apply to persisting physical objects, according to Berkeley, in a way which is derivative of their more basic application to our fleeting ideas, which are their temporal, and ‘personal’, parts. 4 Having said that, I believe that there are significant, and illuminating, structural similarities between the latter Berkeleyian view, and Lewis’ (1998) account of the metaphysics of persisting (that is, in his view, perduring, rather than enduring) macroscopic physical objects, especially in the presence of his Ramseyian humility (2002). My forthcoming ‘Berkeley and Modern Metaphysics’, and Perception and its Objects, contain detailed development of this suggestion.
the referent of a perceptual content in which F is predicated. I call this the Content View, (CV), since it characterizes perceptual experience by its representational content, and identifies the objects of perception as those to which reference is made by such contents. (CV) rejects (3) from my opening inconsistent triad, by rejecting the early modern empiricist idea which gives the notion of a direct object its sense: there are no direct objects in this sense.
I believe that (CV) is a mistake. My aim in this paper is to begin a rehabilitation of the early modern empiricist insight, as I see it, that the core subjective character of perceptual experience is simply constituted by the objects presented in that experience. I argue that this is perfectly consistent with the empirical realist contention, even in cases of illusion, that these direct objects are the persisting mind-independent physical objects we all know and love. I call this the Object View (OV). (OV) also rejects (3), this time by insisting that the direct objects crucial to understanding perception, as the early modern empiricists contend, are perfectly mind-independent physical things.
I begin, though, with a brief sketch of what I regard as a series of highly suggestive problems which (CV) encounters in reconciling its approach to illusion, in terms of false representational content, with the idea that the objects of visual illusion are themselves subjectively presented in such experience. 5 The fundamental intuition is that (CV) induces a significant distortion, by forcing materials pertaining to a person’s conceptual
5 My forthcoming ‘Perception and Content’, and Perception and its Objects, contain extended critical investigation of (CV), in which the following difficulties are developed at length. ↩︎
thought about the world presented in perception into its account of the most basic nature of perceptual experience itself. Selective categorization of particular constituents of physical reality enters the picture of a person’s relation with the world around her only when questions of their various similarities with, and differences from, other such things somehow become salient in thought about them, rather than constituting an essential part of their basic subjective presentation in perception. Perception itself constitutes the fundamental ground for the very possibility of any such abstract general thought about the physical world subjectively presented in it. In assimilating experience to thought, (CV) misses what is fundamental to its subjective character.
Consider the Müller-Lyer illusion, (ML), for example, in which two lines which are actually identical in length are made to look different in length by the addition of misleading hashes. Rejecting any appeal to two mind-dependent items which actually differ in length, as we surely must, the proponent of (CV) insists that we describe this as a case in which the two lines are falsely represented in visual experience as being of unequal length.
Is the line with inward hashes supposed to be represented as shorter than it actually is, though; or is the line with outward hashes represented as longer than it actually is; or both; and by how much in each case? That is to say, how exactly would the world have to be for the purported perceptual representation to be veridical? (CV)'s talk of perceptual content requires a specific answer to this question. Yet it far from clear how one is nonarbitrarily supposed to be given.
It might be replied that perception represents the (ML) lines, merely determinably, as one a little longer than the other, rather than assigning either a very determinate length or any real determinacy to the degree of their difference in length. This comes at a cost, though, for it forfeits the (CV) theorist’s preferred account of the fine-grainedness of perception, crucial to distinguishing experiential representation from representation in thought, on this approach, as consisting in the maximal degree of determinateness in perceptual content, as opposed, often at least, to the more determinable contents which figure in thought (see e.g. Evans, 1982, p. 229; Peacocke, 1992; McDowell, 1994, Lect. III and Afterword, Pt. II; Brewer, 1999, 5.3.1).
Now, consider the four endpoints of the two main lines in the (ML) diagram. Surely these may experientially be represented as being where they actually are, at just those four places in space, according to (CV). Indeed, looking at the diagram head-on, in good viewing conditions, and raising the question in turn where each endpoint looks to be, (CV) seems to me to be committed to this description. At the same time, the illusory nature of the experience supposedly consists in the fact that the lines are also represented as being different in length. In that case, the representational content of the (ML) experience is impossible. It cannot possibly be veridical, not even when faced by the diagram itself, in perfect viewing conditions. This strikes me as an unattractive result. For surely one is seeing precisely what is there - lines on the screen just where they are and nowhere else - however misleading that very diagram may be.
There is a further, related, tension, in my view, between the (CV) approach to illusion as false perceptual representation, and the idea that the physical objects of illusion are genuinely subjectively presented in illusory experience. The scope for error introduced by the account of illusion threatens to undermine the phenomenon of perceptual presentation. I can certainly think, of a figure which you hide behind a screen, that it is square, when actually it is circular; but, if we insist on characterizing my perceptual experience as a representation as of a square figure before me, then how can we simultaneously claim that what is actually a circle is thereby subjectively presented to me, even if there actually is a circle out there, where I represent a square as being, which is somehow causally relevant to my purported perceptual representation? Although error in predication of this kind, or far worse, is no obstacle to reference in thought, it makes a mockery of presentation in experience.
I suggest, then, that illusion forces us to distinguish two quite different levels in perception. (OV), as I shall develop it, respects this, in distinguishing the mindindependent direct object, which constitutes the core subjective character of the experience, from the various ways in which this might perfectly intelligibly be taken to be, seen from the subject’s point of view in the given circumstances of perception, and so on, in virtue of its visually relevant similarities with paradigms of various kinds. (CV) is torn, though, between, either leaving the mind-independent object itself out of the subjective picture altogether - as in the case of the circle itself, supposedly seen as a square, above - or forcing both into an impossible representational content - as in the
case of the (ML) lines simultaneously represented as extended between equally distant endpoints, and yet unequal in length.
So, what is the Object View, and how does it account for illusion? The basic idea is that the core subjective character of perceptual experience is given simply by citing the physical object which is its mind-independent direct object. From various points of view, and in various circumstances of perception, physical objects have visually relevant similarities with paradigms of various kinds of such things. These may intelligibly lead us to take them as instances of such kinds when seen from the relevant points of view in the circumstances in question. Thus, they look various ways to us. Illusions are cases in which the direct object of experience has such similarities with paradigms of a kind of which it is not in fact an instance.
For example, the (ML) diagram is visually-relevantly similar to a pair of lines, one longer and more distant than its plane, one shorter and less distant, projecting into the diagram itself on the plane. It is therefore perfectly intelligible how someone seeing it might take that very diagram as consisting of unequal lines, regardless of whether she does or not. In this sense: they look unequal in length.
Which similarities are visually relevant, though; for anything has unrestricted similarities with everything? Clearly, the visually relevant similarities cannot be defined as identities in the ways the relata are visually represented as being, or else (OV) depends upon (CV). That is to say, we cannot simply say that two objects have visually relevant similarities
just when there are sufficiently many common properties amongst those which each is visually represented as having. Rather, they are, according to (OV), to be what ground and explain the ways in which the relata may intelligibly be taken to be when seen. That is to say, two objects have visually relevant similarities when they share sufficiently many common properties amongst those which have a significant involvement in the physical processes underlying vision. Thus, and very crudely, visually relevant similarities are identities in such things as, the way in which light is reflected from the objects in question, in the given circumstances, and propagated to the subject’s viewpoint. 6
What are the paradigms of physical kinds supposed to be? Again very roughly, these are instances of the kinds in question, whose association with the terms for those kinds partially constitutes our understanding of them, given our training in the acquisition of the relevant concepts: paradigm exemplars of the kinds in question relative to our grasp of the concepts for those kinds. 7
I claim that the same account covers many of the most standard cases of visual illusion. Here is a second example, for further illustration, and also to set the scene for my discussion of an illuminating line of objection below.
6 I entirely acknowledge that this is a very rough placeholder for what must in the end by a far more developed account of visually relevant similarities.
7 This idea is clearly in need of far more extended discussion. It also involves a controversial account of concepts and their possession. To make progress here I will have to leave further elucidation and defence for another occasion; but see Fodor (1998) for strong opposition. ↩︎
A white piece of chalk illuminated with red light looks red. Again, the (OV) proposal is that the core of the subjective character of such illusory experience is constituted by that very piece of chalk itself: a particular persisting mind-independent physical object. From the viewpoint in question, and given the relevant perceptual circumstances - especially the abnormally red illumination - it looks red. This consists in the fact that it has visually relevant similarities with paradigm red objects: the light reflected from it is like that reflected from such paradigms in normal viewing conditions.
How does (OV) account for hallucinations, in which nothing physical is subjectively presented. These have no mind-independent direct object. (OV) also rejects any characterization of hallucination in terms of purportedly mind-dependent direct objects. Rather, hallucinatory experiences have to be characterized by giving a qualitative description of a mind-independent scene, and saying that the subject is having an experience which she cannot distinguish by introspection alone from one in which the constituents of such a scene are the direct objects. No more positive characterization of the experience may be given. 8
Now, hallucinations may be caused in many and varied ways, such as by taking certain drugs or getting a firm knock to the head. Other ways of bringing about hallucination may also involve distal external objects, sometimes relatively systematically. Indeed, this may even occur in cases in which the relevant mind-independent objects are also presented as direct objects of vision, supplemented, as it were, by their hallucinatory
8 I rely heavily here upon Martin (2004). ↩︎
products. (OV) has the resources to account for some cases which may pretheoretically be classified as illusions in this way. Hermann’s Grid, in which pale grey patches appear at the intersections of the white channels formed by a grid of closely spaced black squares, is plausibly a case in point.
You might object at this point that, in rejecting (CV), and insisting that the core subjective character of perceptual experience is to be given simply by citing its mindindependent direct object, given the relevant point of view and circumstances of perception, (OV) misses entirely the crucial point: illusions like (ML) are experiential. The (ML) lines look, phenomenologically, unequal in length! 9 I agree with the datum, but I disagree that only (CV), and not (OV), may accommodate it.
This can be illustrated by reflection on the phenomenon of aspect-seeing. In the most basic case, the concept ‘duck’ is intelligibly applicable on being presented with a particular mind-independent animal as the direct object of perception, in virtue of its visually relevant similarities with paradigms of duckhood. In this sense, it looks like a duck. Given the actual direct object involved, with its visually relevant similarities to what we take to be paradigms of duckhood, we can even apply this characterization of the experience to a child without the concept of a duck, if we wish, although the charactrerization makes essential reference to the paradigms constitutive of our grasp of that concept. All that is involved in her having the experience, though, is that that very animal is presented, with the similarities it actually has with various paradigms of ours,
9 Thanks to Ian Phillips (draft) for pressing this objection very forcefully in his paper at the 2005 Warwick University Mindgrad conference. ↩︎
not that her experience in any way represents it as being any such way. Reference to that object, given her viewpoint and the relevant circumstances entirely captures this phenomenology. Noting the intelligible applicability of our concept of a ‘duck’, in virtue of the de facto similarities with our paradigm, we may see it as a duck. This is a further genuinely phenomenological affair; but the difference in how things are for us phenomenologically is no change in the core subjective character of the experience; it rather concerns our classificatory engagement with what is presented to us in it: that very duck. This is the phenomenology of conceptual categorization, or recognition, not that of basic experiential presentation, which is common throughout. Still, it is aptly titled phenomenology, all the same.
Similarly, suppose that I am presented with the duck-rabbit diagram (Jastrow, 1900; Wittgenstein, 1958). According to (OV) the core subjective character of my experience is given simply by that diagram itself. It actually has visually relevant similarities with my paradigms of both a duck and a rabbit. In this sense both concepts are intelligibly applicable, and it looks like both a duck and a rabbit, regardless of whether I notice either resemblance: perhaps it is presented at a peculiar angle, and I notice neither. Then I see it as a duck, say, this is again a phenomenological change, but one of conceptual classificatory engagement with the very diagram presented to me. Similarly, when I shift aspects, and see it as a rabbit, there is an alteration in this phenomenology of the categorization of what is presented.
Consider now the case of (ML). Suppose that someone has the diagram visually presented to them, from head-on, and in good lighting conditions, with eyes open and a normally functioning visual system. According to (OV), the core subjective character of their visual experience is simply constituted by that diagram itself. From that viewpoint, and given the circumstances of perception, it has visually relevant similarities with a paradigm pair of unequal lines at different depths. In this sense, the concept of inequality in length is intelligibly applicable to its main lines, they look unequal in length. Again, we may even mark the de facto existence of these similarities by saying this of children or animals without the relevant concepts. This is genuine phenomenology, which flows directly from the identification of the direct object of the experience, given the viewpoint and relevant circumstances. It is fully captured by (OV) without any need for (CV). Possessing the concept, as I do, I may notice the intelligible applicability of ‘unequal in length’ to the direct object of my (ML) experience. This may be, either because the question of the relative length of its main lines becomes relevant, and I attend accordingly, having previously only been concerned with selecting the black figures from a range of differently coloured diagrams, say, or simply because the intelligible applicability of this concept jumps out at me, or captures my attention. In this more robust sense, the lines now look unequal in length to me, regardless of whether I actually judge them to be so. This is a perfectly genuinely phenomenological matter; but one which is again captured entirely by (OV), along with my deployment of attention and active conceptual endowment, without any need for (CV).
Return, now, to the case of a white piece of chalk illuminated with red light. I explained the way in which (OV) accounts for the fact that this illusorily looks red. (OV) appears equally committed to the claim that it looks white-in-red-light. For everything has visually relevant similarities with itself, however exactly these are to be defined; and this may well be a paradigm case some something which is white-in-red-light. This plausibly entails that the chalk looks white, simpliciter, which is suspect, at best. Furthermore, parity of reasoning presumably suggests that (OV) is committed to the idea that a red piece of chalk in normal lighting conditions looks white-in-red-light, and therefore looks white too. This is surely completely unacceptable. 10
Let me make a start at least on these difficult and fascinating cases by making explicit a distinction implicit in my discussion of aspect seeing. There are thin and thick notions of looking E:o thinly looks E in an experience iff o is its direct object and o simply has visually relevant similarities with paradigm E 's; o thickly looks E iff o thinly looks E and the visually relevant similarities are salient for the subject. A suitable squiggle thinly looks quarter-note-rest-shaped to all of us; thickly only to some - those who recognize it (at least an attempt at) such. The duck-rabbit thinly looks both duck-like and rabbit-like; thickly at most one of these. The locution is I think standardly interpreted thickly, although the thin reading can certainly be made appropriate. When we see white chalk in red light, it thinly looks white-in-red-light, as well as red; it is very unlikely thickly to do so, without considerable stage setting; but then it may well be right to say it does: for example, when trying to pick out the white piece from a collection of differently coloured
10 Many thanks to Anil Gupta, who raised this line of objection in his wonderful comments at the Pacific APA, 2006, in Portland. ↩︎
chalks in a setting in which we all know the light is abnormally red. The correct target looks white (in-red-light). A red piece of chalk in normal lighting also thinly looks white-in-red-light, as well as red. It would not normally thickly look so; but, again, given sufficient stage-setting, it may be brought to do so. Notice, though, that the sense in which the white chalk in red light, and the red chalk is normal light, thickly look white, when they do, given sufficient stage setting, is essentially indirect, involving an explicit conjunction elimination by the subject from salient similarities with a complex paradigm: of something white-in-red-light. Still, it seems to me that all this serves to confirm, rather than in any way undermine, the (OV) contention that various looks are the product of a stable core subjective character and varying, sometimes quite sophisticated, attentional/classificatory phenomena.
Far more should also be said about the role of intelligibility in (OV). What is it for o to be such that it may intelligibly be taken to be E in virtue of its visually relevant similarities with paradigm E 's? 11 This is, neither for the visually relevant similarities to cause the subject to judge that o is F, nor for explicit reference to such similarities to figure in her reasoning to this conclusion. The former is neither necessary nor sufficient. We don’t judge the (ML) lines of different lengths; and paranoia may produce judgements that everything is deadly, even though only some things really look it. The latter is certainly not necessary either. The (ML) lines thickly look different in length even to those without any idea of the explanation I gave. All I can offer here is this. In certain cases, when de facto visually relevant similarities bring the concept F to mind, categorization of the
11 A second question from Gupta. ↩︎
object presented as an E strikes the subject as appropriate given the paradigms of E involved in her acquisition and understanding of that concept. The intelligibility involved here is that of retrospectively evident, appropriate subsumption of a particular under a general term, given the subject’s understanding of the term in question. In such cases, o is intelligibly taken to be E.
I end with two concerns about whether my own final position is really an Object View, on the model of the early modern empiricists, or whether it is not better characterized as a variant of the currently orthodox Content View. 12
First, given all the genuinely phenomenological complexities introduced by attention and classification, what is the force of the (OV) mantra that the presented mind-independent physical objects constitute the core subjective character of perceptual experience. I clearly reject the early modern empiricist proposal that phenomenology fixes, and is fixed by, the properties of direct objects, which are therefore bound to be mind-dependent things. So what is the residual point of the constitution claim? I believe that perceptual experience makes thought about presented mind-independent physical objects possible: our grasp of which things these are is derived from experience. 13 This does not depend upon the classical empiricist biconditional, that something looks E in an experience iff the sense-datum constitutive of that experience is E. The relation which (OV) proposes, between the way things look in experience and the natures of the physical objects
12 The first of these engages a third issues raised by Gupta in Portland; the second was raised by Nicolas Bullot’s very helpful comments at the Pacific APA.
13 See Campbell, 2002, for a sustained and detailed development of this fundamkental empiricist conviction. ↩︎
presented in them, is nevertheless sufficiently tight to persist with the notion of constitution. In the ideal case, something looks F because o is presented in that experience and o is F. In illusory cases, o is presented, and, although not actually F,o is visually relevantly similar to paradigm F 's in ways which may come to be appreciated and understood by the subject. Either way, the nature of o provides a fully perspicuous explanation of the subjective nature of the experience of it, given the point of view and other circumstances involved. O is the object which explains, in a way which is accessible to the subject, how things look. In this sense, it constitutes the core subjective character of his experience. Of course, like ‘intelligibility’ above, and indeed relatedly, ‘perspicuity’ here is in need of serious explication. The kind of explanation I have in mind as perspicuous has its paradigm in Locke’s (1975) mechanistic talk of cogs turning in a clock or keys in a lock, in contrast with the non-perspicuous explanation involved in modern fundamental physical appeals to brute correlations amongst unobservables. The fact that a circular glass top looks elliptical from a certain angle, say, is akin to the former and quite unlike the latter, although I acknowledge that this is well short of any proper characterization of the relatively a priori status of perspicuous explanation.
Second, my own characterization of illusions involves categorization: they are experiences in which o looks F although o is not F. Yet this surely entails an assimilation of (OV) to (CV). Perhaps; but it does not collapse (OV) into a version of (CV). For (CV) attempts to capture the most basic subjective character of perceptual experience in wholly contentful terms, whereas (OV) explains the truth of looks claims, involving the categorization which they clearly do, as the product of a more basic subjective
presentation of a particular object, along with its salient visually relevant similarities with various paradigms in the circumstances.
Consider analogously Grice on conversational implicature (1989a, 1989b). It is a datum that we communicate a highly complex message in speaking a language which our audience understand. Grice’s opponents regard every aspect of this as part of an undifferentiated notion of meaning. Grice insists, on the contrary, upon a partition into core semantic meaning and any pragmatic implicature which may be conveyed by choosing to say something with just those truth-conditions in the circumstances, given the conventions governing good communication. Similarly, I claim that, although ‘unequal in length’, for example, really is part of how the (ML) lines look, it is right to regard this as the product of a more basic subjective presentation of those very lines themselves, along with an account of how they may intelligibly strike us, from that viewpoint, in those conditions, given our training, conceptual endowment, attention and interests at the time. Looks in general flow from the core early modern empiricist insight at the heart of (OV), given independently motivated additional theoretical materials. They are not to be accommodated by any direct and undifferentiated appeal to a barrage of perceptual contents which are simply served up to us in experience. Thus, I claim that the (OV)/(CV) contrast remains robust.
I conclude that (3) is to be rejected. We need not, nor is it in the end defensible to, reject (3) by resorting to today’s (CV) orthodoxy, though. (1) and (2) are true absolutely as they are. The phenomena of illusion, and indeed hallucination, are perfectly compatible with
the idea that mind-independent physical objects are the direct objects of perception, in my sense of themselves constituting the core subjective character of perceptual experience. Content only enters the characterization of perception as a result of an intellectual abstraction or generalization from the basic nature of such experience. In this way, I claim, empirical realism is fully vindicated. 14
References
Berkeley, G. 1975a. Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous. In M. Ayers (ed.), George Berkeley: Philosophical Works. London: Everyman.
- 1975b. A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge. In M. Ayers (ed.), George Berkeley: Philosophical Works. London: Everyman.
Brewer, B. 1999. Perception and Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Forthcoming. ‘Berkeley and Modern Metaphysics’.
- Forthcoming. ‘How to Account for Illusion’. In A. Haddock and F. Macpherson (eds.), Disjunctivism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Forthcoming. ‘Perception and Content’. European Journal of Philosophy.
- Forthcoming. Perception and its Objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Campbell, J. 2002. Reference and Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
14 Many thanks to Justin Broackes, Nicolas Bullot, Steve Butterfill, John Campbell, David Charles, Bill Child, Tim Crane, Imogen Dickie, Naomi Eilan, Anil Gupta, John Hawthorne, Christoph Hoerl, Hemdat Lerman, John McDowell, Jennifer Nagel, Johannes Roessler, Nick Shea, Alison Simmons, Paul Snowdon, Matt Soteriou, Helen Steward, Charles Travis, Ralph Wedgwood, Michael Williams, and Tim Williamson, for helpful comments on previous versions of this material. ↩︎
Evans, G. 1982. The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Fodor, J. 1998. Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Grice, H. P. 1989a. ‘Logic and Conversation’. In his Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
- 1989b. ‘Further Notes on Logic and Conversation’. In his Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Jastrow, J. 1900. Fact and Fable in Psychology. New York: Houghton Mifflin. Lewis, D. 1998. ‘The Problem of Temporary Intrinsics: an Excerpt from On the Plurality of Worlds’. In P. Van Inwagen and D. W. Zimmerman (eds.), Metaphysics: The Big Questions. Oxford: Blackwell.
-
- ‘Ramseyan Humility’. Gareth Evans Memorial Lecture to Oxford University, delivered posthumously by Stephanie Lewis, 2.iii. 02 .
Locke, J. 1975. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
McDowell, J. 1994. Mind and World. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press. Martin, M. 2004. ‘The Limits of Self-Awareness’. Philosophical Studies, 120, 37-89. Peacocke, C. 1992. ‘Scenarios, Concepts and Perception’. In T. Crane (ed.), The
Contents of Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Phillips, I. Draft. ‘Illusion and Content’. Paper presented at the 2005 Warwick University Mindgrad Conference.
Snowdon, P. 1992. How to Interpret “Direct Perception”'. In T. Crane (ed.), The
Contents of Perception. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Stoneham, T. 2002. Berkeley’s World. Oxford University Press.
Wittgenstein, L. 1958. Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.
References (21)
- Berkeley, G. 1975a. Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous. In M. Ayers (ed.), George Berkeley: Philosophical Works. London: Everyman.
- - 1975b. A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge. In M. Ayers (ed.), George Berkeley: Philosophical Works. London: Everyman.
- Brewer, B. 1999. Perception and Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press. - Forthcoming. 'Berkeley and Modern Metaphysics'.
- - Forthcoming. 'How to Account for Illusion'. In A. Haddock and F. Macpherson (eds.), Disjunctivism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- - Forthcoming. 'Perception and Content'. European Journal of Philosophy.
- - Forthcoming. Perception and its Objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Campbell, J. 2002. Reference and Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Many thanks to Justin Broackes, Nicolas Bullot, Steve Butterfill, John Campbell, David Charles, Bill Child, Tim Crane, Imogen Dickie, Naomi Eilan, Anil Gupta, John Hawthorne, Christoph Hoerl, Hemdat Lerman, John McDowell, Jennifer Nagel, Johannes Roessler, Nick Shea, Alison Simmons, Paul Snowdon, Matt Soteriou, Helen Steward, Charles Travis, Ralph Wedgwood, Michael Williams, and Tim Williamson, for helpful comments on previous versions of this material.
- Evans, G. 1982. The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Fodor, J. 1998. Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Grice, H. P. 1989a. 'Logic and Conversation'. In his Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
- - 1989b. 'Further Notes on Logic and Conversation'. In his Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
- Jastrow, J. 1900. Fact and Fable in Psychology. New York: Houghton Mifflin.
- Lewis, D. 1998. 'The Problem of Temporary Intrinsics: an Excerpt from On the Plurality of Worlds'. In P. Van Inwagen and D. W. Zimmerman (eds.), Metaphysics: The Big Questions. Oxford: Blackwell.
- - 2002. 'Ramseyan Humility'. Gareth Evans Memorial Lecture to Oxford University, delivered posthumously by Stephanie Lewis, 2.iii.02.
- Locke, J. 1975. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P. H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- McDowell, J. 1994. Mind and World. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
- Martin, M. 2004. 'The Limits of Self-Awareness'. Philosophical Studies, 120, 37-89.
- Peacocke, C. 1992. 'Scenarios, Concepts and Perception'. In T. Crane (ed.), The Contents of Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Phillips, I. Draft. 'Illusion and Content'. Paper presented at the 2005 Warwick University Mindgrad Conference.
- Snowdon, P. 1992. How to Interpret "Direct Perception"'. In T. Crane (ed.), The Contents of Perception. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.