Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Outline

VENUS'S TEMPLE: PLEASURE AND POLITICS IN MONTESQUIEU

2024, History of Political Thought

Abstract

Liberty is Montesquieu's decisive political good, and so contemporary scholarship often debates which political path he thought best to secure it. But as for why liberty is good, most scholars leave that question unexamined. In this article I argue that Montesquieu justifies liberty and politics by a romantic hedonism, and we understand this hedonism if we compare him to the ancient hedonist he most admired, Lucretius. Uniting Montesquieu's best-known works and restoring his neglected Temple of Gnidus, this article explores the reasoning behind Montesquieu's political thought, the paradoxes that result, and a twist in Lucretius's early-modern reception.

References (47)

  1. N.K. GILMORE takes her epigraph from Polignac, would add René Descartes, whom she calls a 'most fervent and explicit Epicurean'; she notes that Descartes' popularizer, Antoine Le Grande, wrote a hymn to Epicureanism -L'epicure spirituel (Wilson, Epicureanism, pp. 98, 266).
  2. Jean-Pierre de Bougainville, 'Discours Préliminaire', in L'Anti-Lucrèce, trans.
  3. Jean-Pierre de Bougainville (2 vols., Paris, 1749), Vol. 1, pp. ix, v, viii, xxii; Ernest Ament, 'The Anti-Lucretius of Cardinal Polignac', Transactions and Proceedings of the American Philological Association, 101 (1970), p. 34. On Montesquieu's related cri- tique of Bayle see Lorenzo Bianchi, '« L'auteur a loué Bayle, en appelant un grand homme » : Bayle dans la Défense de L'Esprit des lois', in Montesquieu, oeuvre ouverte? (1748-1755), ed. Catherine Larrère (Naples, 2005), pp. 103-14.
  4. Bougainville, 'Discours Préliminaire', Vol. 1, pp. x-xx, xxiv-v; cf. Holley, 'Eighteenth-Century French Epicureanism', pp. 1108-15; Jared Holley, 'Rousseau on Refined Epicureanism and the Problem of Modern Liberty', European Journal of Political Theory, 17 (2018), pp. 413-17; Palmer, Reading Lucretius, pp. 238-41.
  5. Melchior de Polignac, L'Anti-Lucrèce, trans. Jean-Pierre de Bougainville (2 vols., Paris, 1749), Vol. 1, pp. 27, 28, 31, 40, 81; cf. Ament, 'The Anti-Lucretius', pp. 36-9.
  6. Montesquieu, My Thoughts, p. 430; cf. p. 159. Polignac's flamboyant, luxurious life seems to contradict his austere arguments (Ament, 'The Anti-Lucretius', pp. 30-2).
  7. SL XXIII.19.439; cf. SL XXIII.23.451, XXIV.1.459, XXIV.19.473. Of the nine Books Polignac finished for the Anti-Lucretius, all but two (I and VII) were on the soul and the universe.
  8. CR X.97; cf. CR XVI.148; SL XXIII.21.447-8.
  9. DRN I.136-7; cf. David Sedley, 'Epicureanism in the Roman Republic', in The Cambridge Companion to Epicureanism, ed. James Warren (Cambridge, 2009), pp. 32-3.
  10. SL XXIII.21.447-8; Montesquieu excepts the Stoics from this accusation (SL XXIV.10-11.465-6). N.K. GILMORE
  11. CR XVI.148.
  12. CR IX.92.
  13. Arnobius, Adversus Gentes IV.29, quoted in Fragmentary Republican Latin, Vol- ume I: Ennius, Testemonia. Epic Fragments, trans. Sander Goldberg and Gesine Manuwald (Cambridge, 2018), p. 76; Augustine, The City of God against the Pagans, trans. R.W. Dyson (New York, 1998), VI.10.261-4.
  14. CR X.98; cf. OC I.81; SL XXIV.2.460-1.
  15. John Scheid, An Introduction to Roman Religion, trans. Janet Lloyd (Indianapolis, 2003), pp. 20-1.
  16. Scheid, however, denies that the civic cult was hopelessly weak in the late Republic (Scheid, The Gods, the State, and the Individual, pp. 1-3, 13-14, 29-34). 58
  17. Bougainville, 'Discours Préliminaire', Vol. 1, p. iv.
  18. SL XXV.13.490-2, XXVI.11-12, 504-5.
  19. As Sullivan discusses well (Sullivan, Despotic Ideas, pp. 117-32).
  20. SL XXIV.2-7.460-4. Callanan (Liberalism, pp. 175-204) and Shackleton (Montes- quieu, pp. 342-53), for example, find Montesquieu favourable to Christianity; Pangle (Philosophy of Liberalism, pp. 249-59; Liberal Modernity, pp. 38-47, 99-108), Schaub (Erotic Liberalism, pp. 17-19, 61-9, 71-6, 100-2), and Jean Starobinski (Montesquieu par lui-même, pp. 26, 55-6) see him as aggressively unchristian; while Rasmussen (Pragmatic Enlightenment, pp. 20, 167, 176-8) and Sullivan (Despotic Ideas, pp. 85-110) fall in between.
  21. CR X.97, XVI.145; SL XXIV.10.466.
  22. SL X.4.142, XIX.10.313; OC II.562. , though she does not men- tion fidelity (Spector, Pouvoirs, richesses et sociétés, pp. 122-6).
  23. SL Author's Foreword xli; cf. SL XII.6.194, XIX.11.314, XXIII.1.427. 101 SL VI.20.94, XVI.11.272, XIX.5.310, XXV.13.490-2.
  24. Cf. Nancy Rosenblum, Another Liberalism: Romanticism and the Reconstruction of Liberal Thought (Cambridge, 1987), pp. 2-4, 35-6, 45-9.
  25. SL XIX.27.325, XIX.5.310.
  26. SL XIX.8.311-12, XXI.5.357.
  27. Fabienne Moore, Prose Poems of the French Enlightenment (London, 2009), p. 104; Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Reveries of the Solitary Walker, trans. Charles Butterworth (Indianapolis, 1992), p. 49; cf. Montesquieu, OEuvres et écrits diverses, ed. 111
  28. Diana Schaub, 'The Education of the Sentiments in Montesquieu's The Temple of Gnidus', in The Arts of Rule: Essays in Honor of Harvey C. Mansfield, ed. Sharon Krause and Mary Ann McGrail (Lanham, 2009), p. 143.
  29. OC I.394; cf. SL Pref. xliv.
  30. OC I.400-1; cf. CR XVIII.168-70; DRN III.1060-70. 114 SL V.18.68. 115 OC I.401.
  31. SL V.14.59; OC II.292. Though he praises pleasure, Montesquieu always blames voluptuousness (SL II.5.20, XV.9.253, XV.12.255). 117 SL X.4.142, X.14.150.
  32. N.K. GILMORE
  33. On the institutional aspects of Montesquieu's liberty, see Craiutu, Courageous Minds, pp. 48-54; and Sharon Krause, 'The Spirit of Separate Powers in Montesquieu', Review of Politics, 62 (2000), pp. 231-65.
  34. Krause, 'History and the Human Soul', p. 260; cf. Krause, 'Despotism', pp. 257-9.
  35. DRN II.642, 647; cf. DRN V.1154-5; Polignac, Anti-Lucrèce, 1: 29-30. For a dif- ferent interpretation, according to which Lucretius takes a certain Socratic approach to religion, see John Colman, Lucretius as Theorist of Political Life (New York, 2012), pp. 26-7, 79, 112-13, 118, 132-5, 142. 121 SL V.2-3.42-3.
  36. Nelson, Greek Tradition, p. 176; cf. SL, IV.4.4.35. N.K. GILMORE
  37. DRN V.1120-39; cf. Polignac, L'Anti-Lucrèce, Vol. 1, p. 61. 132 SL III.6.26.
  38. SL III.7.27.
  39. SL IV.2.32; OC II.262; cf. SL XXVIII.22.561-2; Schaub, Erotic Liberalism, pp. 148-50. 135 SL IV.2.33; Krause, 'Politics of Distinction', p. 477. 136 SL VIII.7.117. 137 SL XX.1.338, XXI.5.357. 138 SL XX.4.340; XXI.7.362-4.
  40. SL XI.4.155; cf. SL II.4.18, III.3.22, VIII.9.118-19, XIX.27.331, XX.22.350-1.
  41. Spector, Pouvoirs, richesses et sociétés, p. 22; cf. Céline Spector, 'Montesquieu était-il libérale?', in La pensée libérale, ed. Gilles Kévorkian (Paris, 2010), pp. 66-8; and Bandoch, Politics of Place, pp. 68-73.
  42. Spector, Pouvoirs, richesses et sociétés, p. 142; cf. Krause, 'Despotism', pp. 238, 241. 142 SL V.18.68.
  43. SL VIII.8-9.118-19, VIII.21.126-8, XVII.6.283-4.
  44. Hobbes, Leviathan, pp. 471, 321; Latin from Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed.
  45. Noel Malcolm (3 vols., Oxford, 2012), Vol. 2, p. 521. Montesquieu had Hobbes's 1668 Opera philosophica in his library. Cf. Sullivan, Despotic Ideas, p. 54. N.K. GILMORE
  46. Jean Ehrard, L'Esprit des mots: Montesquieu en lui-même et parmi les siens (Geneva, 1998), pp. 13-14; Clifford Orwin, 'Montesquieu's Humanité and Rousseau's Pitié', in Montesquieu and His Legacy, ed. Rebecca Kingston (Albany, 2008), pp. 139-48. 146 DRN I.929-34.
  47. SL Pref. xliv; cf. SL I.1.5, XXIX.19.618. 148 SL Pref. xlv, XII.6.194, XXIV.7.464; OC II.1152. 149 SL XII.2.188.