Causal Exclusion and Overdetermination
2013, International Philosophical Quarterly
https://doi.org/10.5840/IPQ201353439Abstract
Jaegwon Kim argues that if mental properties are irreducible with respect to physical properties, then mental properties are epiphenomenal. I believe that this conditional is false and argue that mental properties, along with their physical counterparts, may causally overdetermine their effects. Kim contends, however, that embracing causal overdetermination in the mental ease should be resisted for at least three reasons: (1) it is implausible, (2) it makes mental properties causally dispensable, and (3) it violates the Causal Closure Principle. I believe, however, that each of these reasons can be defeated. Moreover, further reflection on (3), according to Kim's implicit logic, may lend support to the claim that physical properties, and not mental properties, are in danger of losing their causal relevance. I. THE CAUSAL EXCLUSION ARGUMENT T HE TARGET OF KIM'S SO-CALLED Causal Exclusion Argument is the family of positions known as non-reductive physicalism. These positions share at least three cardinal commitments: (1) mental properties are distinct from and irreducible with respect to physical properties, (2) mental properties are causally efficacious, and (3) mental properties metaphysically supervene on physical properties. I will call these commitments: distinctness, efficacy, and supervenience, respectively. With this in mind, let's take a closer look at Kim's Causal Exclusion Argument. Suppose that there is a case of mental-to-mental causation between two different mental properties, M, and M^. According to supervenience we know that M^ must have a physical supervenience base P^ that guarantees M^'s instantiation. So we have the following two premises: (1) M, causes Mj (2) M^ has some physical property P^ as its supervenience base Kim notes that we are already confronted with a tension generated from the juxtaposition of (1) and (2). He writes: (1) and (2) together give rise to a tension when we consider the question "Why is [MJ instantiated on this occasion? What is responsible for, and explains, the fact that [MJ occurs on this occasion?" For there are two seemingly exclusionary answers: (a) "because [M,] caused [M^] to instantiate on this occasion," and (b) "Because [P^], a supervenience base of [M ] is instantiated on this occasion."'
References (1)
- M, causes Mj (2) M^ has some physical property P^ as its supervenience base Kim notes that we are already confronted with a tension generated from the juxta- position of (1) and (2). He writes: (1) and (2) together give rise to a tension when we consider the question "Why is [MJ instantiated on this occasion? What is responsible for, and explains, the fact that [MJ occurs on this occasion?" For there are two seemingly exclusionary answers: (a) "because [M,] caused [M^] to instantiate on this occasion," and (b) "Because [P^], a supervenience base of [M ] is instantiated on this occasion."'