Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Outline

Lessons from Causal Exclusion1

2010, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research

https://doi.org/10.1111/J.1933-1592.2010.00382.X

Abstract

Madison "Let us now turn to an argument designed to show that mind-body supervenience itself leads to apparent difficulties with mental causation," says Kim (1998: 39). This is something of a reversal, for Kim (1984: 103) had earlier argued that supervenient causation is a legitimate form of causation. I prefer Kim's earlier way of thinking. The problem that Kim, in his more recent writings, sees emerging from supervenience is that of causal exclusion. But I think that supervenience by itself does not entail causal exclusion. Belief that it does betrays a metaphysical prejudice that some empirically-informed reflection may help remove. In this paper I take an empirical perspective toward Kim's arguments for causal exclusion and conclude that, from this perspective, supervenience does not have the dire consequences for causal explanation in the specials sciences that Kim thinks it does. The argument to which Kim refers is this (1998: 38-47): 1) Suppose that minds supervene on brains. 2) Consider a case in which an instance of mental property M causes an instance of M*. 3) By (1), M* has supervenience base P*. 4) But then, by (2) and (3), there are two reasons M* is instantiated: because M caused it and because P* is instantiated on this occasion. 5) But, P* is nomologically sufficient for M* and M*'s presence is not possible unless some supervenience base is present. 6) Hence, if M causes M* it must do so by way of causing M*'s supervenience base which, on this occasion, is P*. 7) But, by (1), M too has a supervenience base, P. 8) Hence, there appear to be two independently sufficient causes of P*: M and P. 9) But, overdetermination is unacceptable. 10) Hence, it must be P that causes P*. 11) Hence, the M to M* and M to P* relations are only apparently causal. A critic might approach this argument from a number of directions. For instance, one might wonder about premise (9). Why is overdetermination unacceptable? Kim has two answers (1998: 44-45). First, if both M and P are sufficient for P*, then M is dispensable, and so an appeal to overdetermination to save the efficacy of the mental in fact has the opposite result. Naturally, this response goes both ways. P too is dispensable. Kim addresses this point in his second answer: if M and P overdetermine then it must be true that were P not present then M would by itself cause P*. But this is a violation of physical causal closure, for it is a case of a nonphysical property instance causing a physical one.

References (7)

  1. Kim, J. (1984): "Epiphenomenal and Supervenient Causation," as reprinted in J. Kim, Supervenience and Mind. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993, pp. 92-108.
  2. Kim, J. (1989): "Mechanism, Purpose, and Explanatory Exclusion," as reprinted in J. Kim, Supervenience and Mind. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993, pp. 237-264.
  3. Kim, J. (1996): Philosophy of Mind. Boulder: Westview Press.
  4. Kim, J. (1998): Mind in a Physical World. Cambridge: MIT Press.
  5. Shapiro, L. and Sober, E. (forthcoming). "Epiphenomenalism --The Do's and Don'ts," in G. Wolters and P. Machamer (eds.), Studies in Causality: Historical and Contemporary (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press).
  6. Weismann, A. (1889): "On Heredity." In Essays upon Heredity and Kindred Biological Problems. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  7. Woodward, J. (2003): Making Things Happen. New York: Oxford University Press.