Wittgenstein, Peirce, and Paradoxes of Mathematical Proof
Analytic Philosophy
https://doi.org/10.1111/PHIB.12177Abstract
Wittgenstein's paradoxical theses that unproved propositions are meaningless, proofs form new concepts and rules, and contradictions are of limited concern, led to a variety of interpretations, most of them centered on rule-following skepticism. We argue, with the help of C. S. Peirce's distinction between corollarial and theorematic proofs, that his intuitions are better explained by resistance to what we call conceptual omniscience, treating meaning as fixed content specified in advance. We interpret the distinction in the context of modern epistemic logic and semantic information theory, and show how removing conceptual omniscience helps resolve Wittgenstein's paradoxes and explain the puzzle of deduction, its ability to generate new knowledge and meaning.
References (42)
- On Dummett's reading, Wittgenstein's position takes on a Heraclitean or Hegelian flavor. According to (Papa-Grimaldi, 1996, p. 312), "the Hegelian logic is not a solution of [Zeno's] paradox but a dismissal of the logical coordinates that generate it". Compare to Dummett's: "Holism is not, in this sense, a theory of meaning: it is the denial that a theory of meaning is possible" (Dummett, 1973, p. 309).
- Relationship between Peirce's and late Wittgenstein's positions is complicated. "Mean- ing is use" is reminiscent of the pragmatic maxim (but qualified as "sometimes, but not al- ways"), and "a way of grasping a rule that is not an interpretation" is akin to Peirce's habit change analysis. However, a detailed examination of the available evidence in (Boncom- pagni, 2016, Ch.1) concludes that "Wittgenstein expresses a basically negative attitude towards pragmatism as a Weltanschauung, but acknowledges affinities with pragmatism as a method". It is known that Wittgenstein read James extensively, and spent a year (1929) working with Ramsey, who developed his own version of semantic pragmatism based on Peirce's early works (Marion, 2012). Boncompagni speculates that Wittgenstein read Peirce's collection Chance, Love, and Logic, Ramsey's source, some time after 1929. Ramsey was also a precursor of epistemic logic, with key ideas developed around 1929.
- There is some oscillation on Wittgenstein's part, noted in (Plebani, 2010, p. 99), as to whether merely having a decision procedure is enough to give meaning.
- Standard abbreviations are used for Wittgenstein's works: PR for Philosophical Re- marks, RFM for Remarks on Foundations of Mathematics, and LFM for Lectures on Foundations of Mathematics.
- There are two different editions of RFM cited in the literature, with different numbering of the remarks. We cite the MIT paperback edition, as does Wright, but not Rodych and Steiner.
- Dummett reaffirmed and elaborated on his modified reading in (Dummett, 1994), which reproduces some passages from his 1973 lecture almost verbatim.
- NEM v:p is a standard abbreviation for The New Elements of Mathematics by Charles S. Peirce, v volume, p page.
- Dummett's solution to the puzzle of deduction is criticized in (Haack, 1982).
- Examples of proofs discussed in RFM include: conversion of strokes into decimals, occurrence of 770/777 in the decimal expansion of π, impossibility of listing fractions in the order of magnitude, impossibility of angle trisection with straightedge and compass, References J. Azzouni. Why do informal proofs conform to formal norms? Foundations of Science, 14: 9-26, 2009.
- A. Boncompagni. Wittgenstein and Pragmatism. On Certainty in the Light of Peirce and James. Palgrave Macmillan, London, 2016.
- R. Brandom. Reply to Jerry Fodor and Ernest Lepore's "Brandom beleaguered". In Bernhard Weiss and Jeremy Wanderer, editors, Reading Brandom, pages 332- 337. Routledge, 2010.
- A. Brigaglia, C. Ciliberto, and C. Pedrini. The Italian school of algebraic geometry and Abel's legacy. In Olav Arnfinn Laudal and Ragni Piene, editors, The Legacy of Niels Henrik Abel, pages 295-347. Springer-Verlag, Berlin-Heidelberg, 2004.
- M. D'Agostino. The philosophy of mathematical information. In Luciano Floridi, editor, The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Information, pages 164-179.
- Taylor & Francis, London, 2016.
- R. Dipert. Peirce, Frege, the logic of relations, and Church's theorem. History and Philosophy of Logic, 5(1): 49-66, 1984.
- M. Dummett. Wittgenstein's philosophy of mathematics. Philosophical Review, 68 (3): 324-348, 1959.
- M. Dummett. The justification of deduction, British Academy lecture. In Truth and Other Enigmas (Duckworth, 1978), pages 290-318, 1973.
- M. Dummett. Wittgenstein on necessity: Some reflections. In P. Clark and B. Hale, editors, Reading Putnam, pages 49-65. Blackwell, Cambridge, MA, 1994.
- M. Giaquinto. Visualizing in mathematics. In Paolo Mancosu, editor, The Philos- ophy of Mathematical Practice, pages 22-42. Oxford University Press, 2008.
- S. Haack. Dummett's justification of deduction. Mind, XCI: 216-239, 1982.
- J. Hintikka. C.S. Peirce's "first real discovery" and its contemporary relevance. The Monist, 63(3): 304-315, 1980.
- M. Jago. Logical information and epistemic space. Synthese, 167(2): 327-341, 2009.
- M. Jago. The content of deduction. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 42(2): 317-334, 2013.
- S. Kripke. Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. Harvard University Press, Oxford, 1982.
- S. Levy. Theoremic/corollarial distinction and the interconnections between math- ematics and logic. In Nathan Houser, Don D. Roberts, and James Van Evra, editors, Studies in the Logic of Charles Sanders Peirce, pages 85-110. Indiana University Press, 1997.
- P. Mancosu. Measuring the size of infinite collections of natural numbers: was Cantor's theory of infinite number inevitable? The Review of Symbolic Logic, 2 (4): 612-646, 2009.
- M. Marion. Wittgenstein, Ramsey, and British pragmatism. European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2:54-80, 2012.
- A. W. Moore. Wittgenstein's later philosophy of mathematics. In Hans-Johann Glock and John Hyman, editors, A Companion to Wittgenstein, pages 319-331. John Wiley & Sons,, 2017.
- M. Murphey. The Development of Peirce's Philosophy. Harvard University Press, 1961.
- A. Papa-Grimaldi. Why mathematical solutions of Zeno's paradoxes miss the point: Zeno's one and many relation and Parmenides' prohibition. The Review of Meta- physics, 50(2):299-314, 1996.
- C. S. Peirce. The New Elements of Mathematics by Charles S. Peirce. Edited by Carolyn Eisele, Humanities Press, Atlantic Highlands, NJ, 1976.
- M. Plebani. Reconsidering Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Mathematics. PhD thesis, Universitá Ca' Foscari Venezia, Venice, 2010.
- G. Priest and R. Routley. First historical introduction. A preliminary history of paraconsistent and dialethic approaches. In Graham Priest, Richard Routley, and Jean Norman, editors, Paraconsistent Logic, Essays on the Inconsistent, pages 3-75. Philosophia Verlag, 1989.
- V. Rodych. Wittgenstein on mathematical meaningfulness, decidability, and appli- cation. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 38(2):195-225, 1997.
- T. L. Short. Peirce's Theory of Signs. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, New York, 2007.
- M. Steiner. Empirical regularities in Wittgenstein's philosophy of mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica (III), 17:1-34, 2009.
- B. Stroud. Wittgenstein and logical necessity. Philosophical Review, 74:504-518, 1965.
- S. Toulmin. The Uses of Argument. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1958.
- L. Wittgenstein. Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics. Dover Publications, New York, 1975a.
- L. Wittgenstein. Philosophical Remarks. Edited by R. Hargreaves and R. White, translated by R. Rhees, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1975b.
- L. Wittgenstein. Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics. Edited by G.H.V. Wright, R. Rhees, translated by G.E.M. Anscombe, MIT paperback edition, Cambridge, Mass, 1967.
- C. Wright. Wittgenstein on the Foundations of Mathematics. Modern Revivals in Philosophy. Gerald Duckworth & Co., England, 1980.