Mental Representations and the Dynamic Theory of Mind
2012, Logos & Episteme
https://doi.org/10.5840/LOGOS-EPISTEME20123328Abstract
In this paper I will investigate the possibility of defending the concept of 'mental representation' against certain contemporary critiques. Some authors, like Anthony Chemero, argue that it is possible to explain offline actions with dynamic concepts. Hence, the dynamic discourse preempts the representational one. I doubt that this is a recommendable strategy. A form of representation is necessary, though one which is different from the classical one. Instead of eliminating the concept of representation (as radical dynamicists do) or of splitting cognitive explanation in two separate discourses (as the adepts of the hybrid cognition version do), I consider that a dynamic concept of 'representation' is a better option. In my view, the higher level order resulted from the complex brain-body-environment coupling can be interpreted as being representational in nature. The dynamic paradigm involves a significant change concerning the intentional nature of representational states: the basic forms of representations are not maps of reality implemented as such in the brain, but limit conditions, attractors constraining the cognitive system's evolution in its space state to reach its goals. On a certain threshold of complexity, the system develops stable attractors and attractor landscapes which could be interpreted as standing for something outside the system. This conception offers the advantages of avoiding preemption argument, of unifying the cognitive explanation and, by its interscalar account, offers dynamic tools for building more complex artificial intelligent systems.
References (13)
- 9 Esther Thelen and Linda Smith, A Dynamic Systems Approach to the Development of Cognition and Action (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1994).
- Elliot Saltzman, "Dynamics and Coordinate Systems in Sensorimotor Activity," in Mind as Motion, 149-174.
- Catherine Browman and Louis Goldstein, "Dynamics and Articulatory Phonology," in Mind as Motion, 175-194.
- Jeffrey Elman, "Language as a Dynamical System," in Mind as Motion, 195-226.
- M. T. Turvey and Claudia Carello, "Some Dynamical Themes in Perception and Action," in Mind as Motion, 373-402.
- Scot Kelso, Dynamic Patterns: The Self-Organization of Brain and Behavior (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1995).
- Hubert Dreyfus, "Merleau-Ponty and Recent Cognitive Science," in The Cambridge Companion to Merleau-Ponty, ed. Taylor Carman (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 129.
- Dreyfus, "Merleau-Ponty," 130.
- John Haugeland, "Representational genera," in Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, eds. William Ramsey, Stephen P. Stich, and David E. Rumelhart (Hillsdale: Erlbaum, 1991), cited in Clark Being There, 144.
- Thimothy van Gelder, "Dynamics and Cognition," in Mind Design II. Philosophy, Psychology, Artificial Intelligence, Revised and enlarged edition, ed. John Haugeland (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1997), 422-429.
- Arthur Markman and Eric Dietrich, "In Defense of Representation," Cognitive Psychology 40 (2000): 148.
- Markman and Dietrich, "In Defense of Representation," 148.
- "(…) systems that learn and make use of prior behavior have some enduring states that allow the system to react to new situations on the basis of past experience." (Markman and Dietrich, "In Defense of Representation," 148.)