Yes, but? Some Skeptical Remarks on Realism and Anti-Realism
1989, dialectica
https://doi.org/10.1111/J.1746-8361.1989.TB00930.X…
19 pages
1 file
Sign up for access to the world's latest research
Abstract
This paper argues that the much discussed issue between "scientific realism" and "instrumentalism" has not been clearly drawn. Particular attention is paid to the claim that only realism can "explain" the success of scientific theories andmore especiallythe progressively increasing success of such theories in a coherent line of inquiry. This claim is used to attempt to reach a clearer conception of the content of the realist thesis that underlies it; but, it is here contended, that attempt fails, and the claim itself hangs in the air. A series of increasingly sophisticated versions of the "instrumentalist" thesis is considered, and both these and the contentions of realism are placed in relation both to particular examples of scientific development and positions historically maintained by philosophers and by scientists. The author's conclusion is that, when the positions are assessed against the background of the actual history of science, (a) each of the contrary doctrines, interpreted with excessive simplicity, is inadequate as a theory of the dialectic of scientific development; (b) each, so interpreted, has contributed in important instances to actual damage to investigations by great scientists (Huygens, Kelvin, PoincarC); whereas (c) in both the theoretical statements and the actual practice of (in the author's opinion) the most sophisticated philosophers/scientists, important aspects of realism and instrumentalism are present together in such a way that the alleged contradiction between them vanishes.
Related papers
Inferences from scientific success to the approximate truth of successful theories remain central to the most influential arguments for scientific realism. Challenges to such inferences, however, based on radical discontinuities within the history of science, have motivated a distinctive style of revision to the original argument. Conceding the historical claim, selective realists argue that accompanying even the most revolutionary change is the retention of significant parts of replaced theories, and that a realist attitude towards the systematically retained constituents of our scientific theories can still be defended. Selective realists thereby hope to secure the argument from success against apparent historical counterexamples. Independently of that objective, historical considerations have inspired a further argument for selective realism, where evidence for the retention of parts of theories is itself offered as justification for adopting a realist attitude towards them. Given the nature of these arguments from success and from retention, a reasonable expectation is that they would complement and reinforce one another, but although several theses purport to provide such a synthesis the results are often unconvincing. In this paper I reconsider the realist's favoured type of scientific success, novel success, offer a revised interpretation of the concept, and argue that a significant consequence of reconfiguring the realist's argument from success accordingly is a greater potential for its unification with the argument from retention. 1 Musgrave (1988) argues that 'careful realists', at least since Whewell, have always intended the verification of novel predictions in discussions of scientific success. Worrall (1989b), , and Psillos (1999) each argue the importance of peculiarly novel success; many recent antirealist arguments also now pay particular attention to such results. 2 The most famous example of the antirealist challenge from the history of science is . Many interpret Laudan as defending a (pessimistic meta-) induction that implies our own theories are destined for replacement by new theories, radically incongruent with our own. Others (for example argue convincingly that Laudan should instead be understood as merely providing examples that at least appear to undermine the credibility of the realist's inference from success to approximate truth. On either interpretation historical considerations present the realist with a significant challenge.
New Approaches to Scientific Realism, 2020
Scientific realism plays a central role in the philosophico-methodological discussions on research. Two are the main directions in the contributions made to scientific realism: the "internal" line and the "external" path. Following the first line, there are new visions of realism focused on central aspects of science: semantic, logic, epistemological, methodological, ontological, axiological, and ethical components. When the route follows the second path, realism in science is seen as interrelated with realism in technology and as connected to a philosophical approach to society. Altogether there is now a plethora of characterizations of scientific realism, and this paper presents the main contemporary versions of scientific realism. The analysis of the central tenets of the recent views on scientific realism contributes to present this book, which offers novelty to the ongoing debate on scientific realism.
Erkenntnis, 1983
Even to the beginning student of the philosophy of science, it is apparent that philosophy has ‘failed to deliver the goods’ (Laudan 1983) of establishing a demarcation criterion between what we call ‘science’ and ‘pseudo-science’; the first task of this essay will be to attempt to explain why such a programme should fail. Following the demise of the demarcation problem, a void has been left in which ‘relativism’ and ‘anti-realism’ has thrived. Countering this, the ‘no miracles argument’ (Putnam 1975) seems to defend a realist interpretation of the theories of science and the entities to which they ‘refer’; the ‘success’ of science could not be explained other than that there is a ‘truth’ content to theories. This essay will show that this realism/antirealism debate is in fact not a real philosophical problem at all; rather, it is a logically ungrounded metaphysical debate – the result of philosophers construing grammatical claims as if they were scientific claims. It will then establish that although realism is an ‘ungrounded’ metaphysical position, unlike antirealism, it actually has an important practical use – it is a position that functions well and is in fact essential within the ‘language game’ of science (Wittgenstein 1953).
2005
It is proposed here that all successful and complete theories always proceed through an intermediate stage of instrumentalism to the final stage of realism. Examples from history of science (both classical and modern) in support of this hypothesis are presented.
Synthese, 2011
The papers collected in this special issue are written versions of talks delivered at the Theoretical Frameworks and Empirical Underdetermination workshop which we organised at the University of Duesseldorf on April 11-12 2008. Early in the summer of 2007 we were still immersed in the planning stages of the workshop. At the time our main concern was to invite philosophers that were making and would continue to make significant contributions to the scientific realism debate. With this aim in mind, we prepared a list of invitees. One of the names at the top was that of Peter Lipton. His work on inference to the best explanation had established him as one of the most prominent and formidable defenders of scientific realism. When Peter accepted the invitation our confidence in the workshop's prospects was greatly enhanced. Alas it was not meant to be. Peter unexpectedly passed away in November 2007. His absence from the workshop was strongly felt not least because quite a few of the participants had known Peter both on a professional as well as on a personal basis. David Papineau was drafted in as a replacement. Since David had a long and entwined history with Peter he was entrusted with the honourable task of delivering a eulogy on the opening day of the workshop. We are very thankful to David for delivering a moving eulogy as well as for agreeing to replace Peter at such short notice. We would like to dedicate this special issue of Synthese to the memory of Peter Lipton, a fellow philosopher and to some of us a dear friend.
This essay will set out the importance of realism to the scientific endeavour; the anti-realist doubts, the realist response and the anti-realist response. It will then look at the common anti-realist positions of instrumentalism and constructive empiricism and discuss a possible third way presented by Fine (1984) the natural ontological attitude (NOA). Finally I will sum up the arguments and proposals as to the future of science with the conclusion that in the light of all the evidence against realism, it is becoming decreasingly tenable. Nevertheless the anti-realist solutions whilst avoiding the main problems of realism may take us too far away from the noble endeavour of science, which is the search for truth of reality.
An axiological claim is taken here to be one that is concerned with the aim of science; for example that science aims for truth, empirical adequacy, or accurate predictions. The argument is that scientific axiological claims are of doubtful value and are not what they appear to be. It is firstly questionable whether there is any one entity called ‘science’ to which these aims can be ascribed. The teleological construal of aim is discussed and rejected, as also is van Fraassen’s proposed construal of ‘aim’ as criterion of success. The conclusion is that the philosopher who attributes an aim to science tells us little about science and much about how they understand the nature of science.
The presented text focuses rather on enabling access to philosophical aspects and ideological residuals found in several scientific approaches and issues. It means, analyses of conceptual schemes but also of phenomena present in their implicitly perceived background are to be dealt with. It is essays on science, its roots, and essence but also on relations of science and philosophy and also on heritage which philosophers left in science that I thematize. And it is in this sense that the presented text represents a textbook. It should try to teach how to comprehend explanatory bases and limits of philosophical and scientific knowledge but also to view things creatively, in other than a traditional way. Its task is to make bases complicated and surmise boundaries, and also to find creatively inspirations and new possible outcomes. The text is a philosophical essay (in the original sense of this word: an examination, (re)consideration, experiment). It is an attempt to ponder on a nature of sciences, methods and procedures, evidences and also on axioms and explanatory bases, but at the same time it represents an attempt to assess them. From this viewpoint, it rather complicates issues than provides answers to them and that is what the author’s intention aspires to: to induce students not to take things for granted and to try to view the world differently from the way they perceived it before. A vision of the world, clarity, looking at and thematizing of an issue which represents amatter of course (and thus which is frequently implicit and beyond doubt), noticing of an issue scientists and philosophers thought and did not thought about, but also why they believed in what they believed that is what represents the main object of the presented research.

Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.