Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Outline

Making sense of essentialism

Abstract
sparkles

AI

This paper critically examines the notion of 'essentialism' in the context of biological classification, particularly through the lens of Carl Linnaeus's work and Ernst Mayr's historical interpretations. It argues against Mayr's portrayal of essentialism as an ideological straitjacket on naturalists, suggesting instead that the practices of naturalists like Linnaeus reveal a more nuanced understanding of species that is not confined to rigid definitions. The discussion extends to the implications of essentialism across various disciplines, including its intersection with human sciences, gender, and identity politics.

References (52)

  1. Mayr, Growth, 38.
  2. Staffan Müller-Wille, Botanik und weltweiter Handel. Zur Begründung eines Natürlichen Systems der Pflanzen durch Carl von Linn'e (1707-1778) (Berlin: Verlag für Wissenschaft und Bildung, 1999); for an English summary of the main results of my dissertation, see Staffan Müller-Wille, 'Collection and Collation: Theory and Practice of Linnaean Botany', Studies in History and Philosophy of the Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 38:3 (2007), 541-562.
  3. Marjorie Grene, 'A defense of David Kitts', Biology and Philosophy, 4:1 (1989), 69-72.
  4. 9 Searching for "essentialism" in title or abstract retrieved 119 items in PubMed, the earliest dating from 1985. Most of the articles came from gender studies, group psychology and science studies. The same search on JSTOR retrieved 283 items, the earliest outside the history and philosophy of biology dating from the mid-1980s as well. For an early review essay that associates the work of Judith Butler, Helen Longino and Robin Fox with Mayr's essentialism story, see Fred Matthews, 'Nature/Nurture, Realism/Nominalism: Our Fundamental Conflict Over Human Identity', Comparative Studies in Society and History 35:3 (1993), 647-662.
  5. Mayr, Growth, 38 and 46.
  6. These three phases roughly correspond to those distinguished by John Beatty, 'The proximate/ultimate distinction in the multiple careers of Ernst Mayr', Biology and Philosophy 9:3 (1994), 333-356.
  7. Carl Chung, Essence, variation, and evolution: An analysis of Ernst Mayr's distinction between 'typological' and 'population' thinking (Ph.D., University of Minnesota, 2000);
  8. Carl Chung, 'On the origin of the typological/population distinction in Ernst mayr's changing views of species, 1942-1959', Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 34 (2003), 277-296.
  9. Ernst Mayr, Systematics and the Origin of Species (New York: Columbia University Press, 1942), 115-122.
  10. Mayr, Systematics, 120; cf. Chun, 'On the origin of the typological/population distinction', 281-285, for a detailed discussion.
  11. Quoted from Chun, 'On the origin of the typological/population distinction', 285.
  12. Ibid., 291-292; cf. Winsor, 'Creation of the essentialism story', 156-157.
  13. Ernst Mayr, 'Karl Jordan's contribution to current concepts in systematics and evolution', Transactions of the Royal Entomological Society of London 107:1-14 (1955), 45-66 (p. 52); cf. Ernst Mayr, 'Species concepts and definitions', in Ernst Mayr (ed.) The Species Problem (Washington D.C.: American Association for the Advancement of Science, 1957), 1-22 (pp. 2-3).
  14. Ernst Mayr, 'Illiger and the Biological Species Concept', Journal of the History of Biology 1:2 (1968), 163-178 (pp. 163-164). Mayr basically maintained this point of view for the rest of his career; see, for example, Mayr, Growth, 260-262.
  15. Mayr, 'Jordan's contribution', 53.
  16. Mayr, 'Illiger', 164; cf. Mayr, 'Footnotes', 198.
  17. Winsor, 'Creation of Essentialism Story,' 165-166.
  18. David L. Hull, 'Ernst Mayr´s Influence on the History and Philosophy of Biology: A Personal Memoir', History of Biology 9:3 (1994), 375-385.
  19. Mayr, 'Footnotes'. This paper was published 1969 in the prestigious journal Philosophy of Science. However, a footnote explains that it was presented 'December 27, 1965, at the annual meeting sponsored by section L of the American Association for the Advancement of Science' where Hull and Mayr met once more; cf. Winsor, 'Creation of Essentialism Story,' 166.
  20. Ernst Mayr, 'Origin and History of Some Terms in Systematic and Evolutionary Biology,' Systematic Zoology 27:1 (1978), 83-88 (p. 85).
  21. The OED lists one earlier reference for essentialism, from a 1939 issue of the journal Modern Philosophical Education, where it is used synonymously with traditionalism in education.
  22. Erika Lorraine Milam, 'The Equally Wonderful Field: Ernst Mayr and Organismic Biology', Historical Studies in the Natural Sciences 40:3 (2010), 279-317 (p. 91).
  23. David L. Hull, 'The Effect of Essentialism on Taxonomy -Two Thousand Years of Stasis (I)', The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 15:60 (1965), 314-326 (p. 314).
  24. Ibid., 316.
  25. David B. Kitts, 'Plato on kinds of animals', Biology and Philosophy 2:3 (1987), 315-328;
  26. Kitts goes so far to maintain that Plato 'hasn't meant to give us a classification of anything' (ibid., 320; the emphasis is his).
  27. Pierre Pellegrin, Les classification des animaux chez Aristote. Statut de la biologie et unité de l´aristotélisme (Paris: Societé d´édition 'Les Belles Lettres', 1982). David M. Balme, 'Aristotle's biology was not essentialist', in Allan Gotthelf and James G. Lennox (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology (Cambridge etc.: Cambridge Univ. Pr., 1987), 291-303.
  28. Hull, 'The Effect of Essentialism', 317-318.
  29. 32 Ernst Mayr, Toward a New Philosophy of Biology: Observations of an Evolutionist (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989), 186; cf. Mayr, 'Darwin and the evolutionary theory', 2; Mayr, 'Growth', 38.
  30. Arthur J. Cain, 'Logic and memory in Linnaeus' system of taxonomy,' Proceedings of the Linnean Society London 169:1-2 (1958), 144-163. Cain's exposition of Linnaeus's taxonomic principles was followed up and further substantiated by James L. Larson, Reason and Experience: The Representation of Natural Order in the Work of Carl Linnaeus (Berkeley etc.: Univ. of California Pr., 1971.
  31. Cain, 'Logic and Memory', 146.
  32. Winsor, 'Creation of Essentialism Story,' 167; cf. Staffan Müller-Wille, 'Collection and Collation: Theory and Practice of Linnaean Botany', Studies in History and Philosophy of the Biological and Biomedical Sciences 38:3 (2007), 541-562.
  33. Mayr, Growth, 640.
  34. Mary P. Winsor, 'Non-essentialist methods in pre-Darwinian taxonomy', Biology and Philosophy 18 (2003), 387-400; cf. James L. Larson, Interpreting Nature: The Science of Living Form from Linnaeus to Kant (Baltimore-London: John Hopkins Univ. Pr., 1994).
  35. Hull, 'The Effect of Essentialism', 317; Karl Popper, The Open Society and Its Enemies. Vol. I: Plato, 4 th edition (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1962), 31.
  36. Elliott Sober, 'Evolution, Population Thinking, and Essentialism', Philosophy of Science 47:3 (1980), 350-383.
  37. Mayr, 'Darwin and the Evolutionary Theory', 2.
  38. Sober, 'Evolution, Population Thinking, and Essentialism', 360-362.
  39. Mayr, 'Joseph Gottlieb Koelreuter´s Contributions to Biology', Osiris. 2nd Series, 2 (1986), 135-176.
  40. Mayr, Toward a New Philosophy of Biology: Observations of an Evolutionist (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989).
  41. Gregor Mendel, Experiments in Plant Hybridisation, edited by James H. Bennett (Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd, 1965), 45-46.
  42. Wilhelm Johannsen, 'The genotype conception of heredity', American Naturalist, 45 (1911), 129-159.
  43. Mayr, 'Where are we?', Cold Spring Harbour Symposia on Quantitative Biology, 24 (1959), 1-14.
  44. See Mayr, Growth, 782-783, on Johannsen, for example.
  45. Staffan Müller-Wille and Vitezslav Orel, 'From Linnaean species to Mendelian factors: Elements of hybridism, 1751-1870', Annals of Science, 64 (2007), 171-215.
  46. Staffan Müller-Wille, 'Hybrids, pure cultures, and pure lines: from nineteenth-century biology to twentieth-century genetics', Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 38:4 (2007), 796-806.
  47. Ernst Hans Gombrich, Norm and Form: Studies in the Art of the Renaissance (New York: Phaidon, 1978), 96; originally published 1966.
  48. Cf. John C. Greene, 'From Aristotle to Darwin: Reflections on Ernst Mayr's Interpretation in "The Growth of Biological Thought"', Journal of the History of Biology, 25:2 (1992), 257- 284.
  49. Müller-Wille, 'The dark side of evolution: caprice, deceit, redundancy', History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 31:2 (2009), 183-199.
  50. See, e. g., Mayr, 'Darwin and the evolutionary theory'.
  51. Popper, Open Society, 8-9.
  52. Mayr, Toward a New Philosophy of Biology, v.