Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Outline

The inapplicability of (selected) paraconsistent logics

https://doi.org/10.1080/11663081.2014.980203

Abstract

In some cases one is provided with inconsistent information and has to reason about various consistent scenarios contained in that information. Our goal is to argue that filtered paraconsistent logics are not the right tool to handle such cases and that the problems generalize to a large class of paraconsistent logics. A wide class of paraconsistent (inconsistency-tolerant) logics is obtained by filtration: adding conditions on the classical consequence operation (one example is weak Rescher-Manor consequence --- which bears $\Gamma$ to $\phi$ just in case $\phi$ follows classicaly from at least one maximally consistent subset of $\Gamma$). We start with surveying the most promising candidates and comparing their strength. Then we discuss the mainstream views on how non-classical logics should be chosen for an application and argue that none of these allows us to chose any of the filtered logics for action-guiding reasoning with inconsistent information, roughly because such a reasoning has to start with selecting possible scenarios and such a process does not correspond to any of the mathematical models offered by filtered paraconsistent logics. Finally, we criticize a recent attempt to defend explorative hypothetical reasoning by means of weak Rescher-Manor consequence operation by Meheus et al.

References (14)

  1. Beall, J. and Restall, G. (2006). Logical Pluralism, volume 78. Oxford University Press.
  2. Benferhat, S., Dubois, D., and Prade, H. (1997). Some syntactic approaches to the handling of inconsistent knowladge bases: A comparative study. Studia Logica, 58:17-45.
  3. Cook, R. T. (2010). Let a thousand flowers bloom: A tour of logical pluralism. Philosophy Compass, 5(6):492-504.
  4. Meheus, J., Straßer, C., and Verdée, P. (2014). Which style of reasoning to choose in the face of conflicting information? Journal of Logic and Compu- tation. (in print).
  5. Payette, G. and Schotch, P. (2009). Preseving what? In On Preserving: Essays on paraconsistent logic, pages 81-99. University of Toronto Press.
  6. Pollock, J. (1995). Cognitive Carpentry. MIT Press.
  7. Prakken, H. (2006). Combining sceptical epistemic reasoning with credulous practical reasoning. In Dunne, P. and Bench-Capon, T., editors, Computa- tionalModels of Argument. Proceedings of COMMA-06., pages 311-322.
  8. Priest, G. (2013). Revising logic. [unpublished paper].
  9. Reggia, J. A., Nau, D. S., and Wang, P. Y. (1985). A formal model of diagnostic inference. i. problem formulation and decomposition. Information Sciences, 37(1):227-256.
  10. Rescher, N. and Manor, R. (1970). On inferences from inconsistent premises. Theory and Decision, 1(2):179-217.
  11. Shapiro, S. (2006). Effectiveness. in. In The Age of Alternative Logics, pages 37-49. Springer.
  12. Simari, G. R. and Loui, R. P. (1992). A mathematical treatment of defeasible reasoning and its implementation. Artificial intelligence, 53(2):125-157.
  13. Urbaniak, R. and Batens, D. (2014). Induction. In Hansson, S. O. and Hen- dricks, V. F., editors, Handbook of Formal Philosophy. Springer. (commis- sioned and forthcoming).
  14. Wyatt, N. (2004). What are beall and restall pluralists about? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82(3):409-420.