Abstract
Recently, it has been objected that naïve realism is inconsistent with an empirically well-supported claim that mental states of the same fundamental kind as ordinary conscious seeing can occur unconsciously (SFK). The main aim of this paper is to establish the following conditional claim: if SFK turns out to be true, the naïve realist can and should accommodate it into her theory. Regarding the antecedent of this conditional, I suggest that empirical evidence renders SFK plausible but not obvious. For it is possible that what is currently advocated as unconscious perception of the stimulus is in fact momentaneous perceptual awareness (or residual perceptual awareness) of the stimulus making the subject prone to judge in some way rather than another, or to act in some way rather than another. As to the apodosis, I show that neither the core of naïve realism nor any of its main motivations is undermined if SFK is assumed. On the contrary, certain incentives for endorsing naïve realism become more tempting on this assumption. Since the main motivations for naïve realism retain force under SFK, intentionalism is neither compulsory nor the best available explanation of unconscious perception. Keywords Unconscious perception • Naïve realism • Intentionalism • Perceptual relation • Consciousness Recently, a number of philosophers have pressed that naïve realism (a.k.a. relationalism) cannot deliver a plausible account of unconscious perception (see e.g. Berger and Nanay 2016; Block 2017; Nanay 2014). The objection assumes that naïve realism is inconsistent with the following claim:
References (63)
- Anaya, A., & Clarke, S. (2017). Naïve realism and unconscious perception: A reply to Berger and Nanay. Analysis, 77(2), 267-273.
- Berger, J., & Nanay, B. (2016). Relationalism and unconscious perception. Analysis, 76(4), 426-433.
- Bermúdez, J. L. (2000). Personal and sub-personal: A difference without a distinction. Philosophical Explo- rations, 3(1), 63-82.
- Block, N. (2010). Attention and mental paint. Philosophical Issues. A Supplement to Noûs, 20, 23-63.
- Block, N. (2012). The grain of vision and the grain of attention. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, 1(3), 170-184.
- Block, N. (2016). The Anna Karenina principle and skepticism about unconscious perception. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 93(2), 452-459.
- Block, N., & Phillips, I. (2017). Debate on unconscious perception. In B. Nanay (Ed.), Current controversies in philosophy of perception (pp. 165-192). New York, London: Routledge.
- Breitmeyer, B. G. (2015). Psychophysical "blinding" methods reveal a functional hierarchy of unconscious visual processing. Consciousness and Cognition, 35, 234-250.
- Brewer, B. (2011). Perception and its objects. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.
- Brogaard, B. (2015). Type 2 blindsight and the nature of visual experience. Consciousness and Cognition, 32, 92-103.
- Burge, T. (2005). Disjunctivism and perceptual psychology. Philosophical Topics, 33(1), 1-78.
- Burge, T. (2010). The origins of objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Burge, T. (2011). Disjunctivism again. Philosophical Explorations, 14(1), 43-80.
- Campbell, J. (2002). Reference and consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Clark, A. (2016). Surfing uncertainty. prediction, action, and the embodied mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Crane, T. (2006). Is there a perceptual relation? In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 126-146). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Dennett, D. (1969). Content and consciousness. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
- Drayson, Z. (2012). The uses and abuses of the personal/subpersonal distinction. Philosophical Perspectives, 26(1), 1-18.
- Fish, W. (2009). Perception, hallucination, and illusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Fish, W. (2010). Philosophy of perception. A contemporary introduction. London: Routledge.
- Frith, C. (2007). Making up the mind. How the brain creates our mental world. London: Blackwell Pub- lishing.
- Gelbard-Sagiv, H., Faivre, N., Mudrik, L., & Koch, C. (2016). Low-level awareness accompanies "uncon- scious" high-level processing during continuous flash suppression. Journal of Vision, 16(1), 1-16.
- Hawthorne, J. (2007). Direct reference and dancing qualia. In T. Alter & S. Walter (Eds.), Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge: New essays on consciousness and physicalism (pp. 195-209). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Hellie, B. (2011). There it is. Philosophical issues, 21(1), 110-164.
- Hellie, B. (2013a). Against egalitarianism. Analysis, 73(2), 304-320.
- Hellie, B. (2013b). It's still there!. In R. Brown (Ed.), Consciousness inside and out: Phenomenology, neuroscience, and the nature of experience (pp. 127-136). Berlin: Springer.
- Hellie, B. (2014a). Love in the time of cholera. In B. Brogaard (Ed.), Does perception have content? (pp. 241-261). New York: Oxford University Press.
- Hellie, B. (2014b). The multidisjunctive conception of hallucination. In F. MacPherson & D. Platchias (Eds.), Hallucination, philosophy and psychology (pp. 149-173). Cambridge, London: MIT Press.
- Hellie, B. (2018). An analytic-hermeneutic history of consciousness. In K. M. Becker & I. Thompson (Eds.), Cambridge companion to history of philosophy 1945-2015. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Jackson, F. C. (1977). Perception: A representative theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Jiang, Y. V., Costello, P., Fang, F., Huang, M., & He, S. (2006). A gender-and sexual orientation-dependent spatial attentional effect of invisible images. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 103(45), 17048-17052.
- Locatelli, R., & Wilson, K. A. (2017). Introduction: Perception without representation. Topoi, 36, 197-212.
- Martin, M. G. F. (2002a). Particular thoughts and singular thought. In A. O'Hear (Ed.), Logic, thought and language (pp. 173-214). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Martin, M. G. F. (2002b). The transparency of experience. Mind and Language, 4(4), 376-425.
- Martin, M. G. F. (2004). The limits of self-awareness. Philosophical Studies, 120(1-3), 37-89.
- Martin, M. G. F. (2006). On being alienated. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 354-410). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Nanay, B. (2012). Perceiving tropes. Erkenntnis, 77(1), 1-14.
- Nanay, B. (2014). Empirical problems with anti-representationalism. In B. Brogaard (Ed.), Does perception have content? (pp. 39-50). New York: Oxford University Press.
- Nanay, B. (2015). The representationalism versus relationalism debate: Explanatory contextualism about perception. European Journal of Philosophy, 23(2), 321-336.
- Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review, 84(3), 231-259.
- Overgaard, M., & Mogensen, J. (2015). Reconciling current approaches to blindsight. Consciousness and Cognition, 32, 33-40.
- Paul, L. A. (2012). Metaphysics as modeling: The handmaiden's tale. Philosophical Studies, 160(1), 1-29.
- Phillips, I. (2016). Consciousness and criterion: On block's case for unconscious seeing. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 93(2), 419-451.
- Phillips, I. (2017). Unconscious perception reconsidered. Retrieved from http://www.ianbphillips.com/ uploads/2/2/9/4/22946642/antwerp.pdf.
- Raio, C., Carmel, D., Carrasco, M., & Phelps, E. A. (2012). Nonconscious fear is quickly acquired but swiftly forgotten. Current Biology, 22(12), 477-479.
- Rosenthal, D. M. (1986). Two concepts of consciousness. Philosophical Studies, 49(3), 329-359.
- Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. London: Hutchinson and Co.
- Schellenberg, S. (2014). The relational and representational character of perceptual experience. In B. Bro- gaard (Ed.), Does perception have content (pp. 199-220). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Schwitzgebel, E. (2008). The unreliability of naive introspection. The Philosophical Review, 117(2), 245- 273. Soteriou, M. (2016). Disjunctivism. London: Routledge.
- Stern, R. (2007). Transcendental arguments: A plea for modesty. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 74, 143- 161.
- Stich, S. P. (1978). Beliefs and subdoxastic states. Philosophy of Science, 45(4), 499-518.
- Travis, C. (2013a). Frege, father of disjunctivism. In: Perception. Essays after Frege (pp. 59-89). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Travis, C. (2013b). Reason's reach. In Perception. Essays after Frege (pp. 118-143). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Travis, C. (2013c). The preserve of thinkers. In Perception. Essays after Frege (pp. 313-363). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Travis, C. (2013d). The silences of the senses. In Perception. Essays after Frege (pp. 23-58). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Travis, C. (2013e). Viewing the inner. In Perception. Essays after Frege (pp. 90-117). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Tye, M. (2007). Intentionalism and the argument from no common content. Noûs, 41(1), 589-613.
- Tye, M. (2014). What is the content of a hallucinatory experience? In B. Brogaard (Ed.), Does perception have content? (pp. 291-310). New York: Oxford University Press.
- Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Windey, B., & Cleeremans, A. (2015). Consciousness as a graded and an all-or-none phenomenon: A conceptual analysis. Consciousness and Cognition, 35, 185-191.
- Wong, H. Y. (2014). Personal and sub-personal: Overcoming explanatory apartheid. In T.-W. Hung (Ed.), Communicative action. Selected papers of the 2013 IEAS conference on language and action. Berlin: Springer.
- Yang, E., Brascamp, J., Kang, M.-S., & Blake, R. (2014). On the use of continuous flash suppression for the study of visual processing outside of awareness. Frontiers in Psychology, 5(724), 1-17.
- Zie ˛ba, P. J. (2017). Unconscious perception and perceptual knowledge. In C. Limbeck-Lilienau & F. Stadler (Eds.), The philosophy of perception and observation. Contributions of the 40th international Wittgen- stein symposium August 6-12, 2017 Kirchberg am Wechsel (pp. 301-303). Kirchberg am Wechsel: ALWS.