Beyond Explication: Meaning and Habit-Change in Peirce's Pragmatism
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-45920-2_11Abstract
In the seminal essay " Pragmatism " , Peirce discusses the end of interpretation in terms of the ultimate logical interpretant, which is varyingly characterized as habit or habit-change. While it is broadly accepted that his conception of pragmatic meaning rests on habit, the precise role of habit-change in his account of conceptual purport has not been examined in detail. In this chapter, I address this issue, which turns out to be closely linked to the pivotal question of the purpose of Peircean pragmatism itself. My primary aim is to demonstrate that Peirce's pragmatic account of the interpretant surpasses that of mere explication of habitual meaning, something that can be teased out from an embryonic account of three logical interpretants, sketched in " Pragmatism " and supported by certain suggestive references to first, second, and third pragmatistic interpretation in other writings. This investigation not only exposes the hitherto overlooked fact that Peirce recognizes a stage of conceptual clarification beyond that of the ultimate logical interpretant; it also paves the way for a reassessment of the significance of the pragmatist approach within a broader developmental-normative framework aimed at the improvements of our habits.
FAQs
AI
How does Peirce's concept of habit redefine the goal of pragmatism?
The research reveals that Peirce defines pragmatism as a method aimed at achieving habit-change, seeing this as the ultimate end of interpretation. This shifts focus from mere clarity of meaning to the proactive development of behaviors and self-control.
What role does the 'ultimate logical interpretant' play in Peirce's theory?
Peirce's 'ultimate logical interpretant' serves as a definitive guide to how concepts inform habitual action. This interpretant is particularly significant as it reflects the culmination of interpretative phases in an individual's cognitive evolution.
What methodological distinctions does Peirce make regarding habit-change?
Peirce distinguishes between natural dispositions and voluntary habits, emphasizing that habit-change encompasses intentional self-modification. This scope includes associative, dissociative, and confirmatory actions, reflecting a complex understanding of cognitive habits.
How does Peirce’s pragmatism address the distinction between internal and public verification?
The paper states that Peirce's pragmatism evolves to acknowledge the necessity of external validation, pushing beyond mere introspective examination. This progression suggests that concepts must withstand public scrutiny to fully develop meaning and impact.
What implications does Peirce's habit-realism have for conceptual clarity?
Peirce's habit-realism posits that the essence of concepts lies in their behavioral implications, thus clarifying meaning through their implications for action. This connects cognitive understanding with practical outcomes, enriching both philosophical discourse and application.
References (29)
- Altshuler, Bruce. 1981. Peirce on progress and meaning. In Proceedings of the C. S. Peirce bicentennial congress, eds. K.L. Ketner et al., 63-69. Lubbock: Texas Tech Press.
- Bergman, Mats. 2012. Improving our habits: Peirce and meliorism. In The normative thought of Charles S. Peirce, eds. C. de Waal and K.P. Skowronski, 125-148. New York: Fordham University Press.
- Bergman, Mats, and Sami Paavola, eds. 2014. The commens dictionary: Peirce's terms in his own words. New Edition. http://www.commens.org/dictionary.
- Colapietro, Vincent M. 1988. Dreams: Such stuff as meanings are made on. VS 49: 65-79.
- Fitzgerald, John J. 1966. Peirce's theory of signs as foundation for pragmatism. The Hague: Mouton.
- Forster, Paul. 2003. The logic of pragmatism: A neglected argument for Peirce's pragmatic maxim. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 39(4): 525-554.
- Gentry, G. 1946. Peirce's early and later theory of cognition and meaning: Some critical comments. The Philosophical Review 55(6): 634-650.
- Houser, Nathan. 2010. The church of pragmatism. Semiotica 178(1/4): 105-114.
- Nöth, Winfried. 2014. The growth of signs. Sign Systems Studies 42(2/3): 172-192.
- Peirce, Charles Sanders. i. 1867-1913. Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A chronological edition. Vols. 1-6 to date, ed. the Peirce Edition Project. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [References to these volumes will be designated by W, followed by volume number, colon, page number.].
- Peirce, Charles Sanders. i. 1867-1913. Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Vols. 1-6, eds. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1931-1935. Vols. 7-8, ed. Arthur W. Burks. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1958. [References to Peirce's papers will be designated by CP, followed by volume, period, paragraph number.].
- Peirce, C.S. 1865-1913. Historical perspectives on Peirce's logic of science: A history of science. 2 vols, ed. C. Eisele. Berlin: Mouton Publishers. [Cited as HP v:p].
- Peirce, C.S. 1865-1914. The new elements of mathematics. 4 vols, ed. C. Eisele. The Hague: Mouton Publishers. [Cited as NEM v:p].
- Peirce, C.S. i. 1867-1893. The essential Peirce: Selected philosophical writing. Vol 1 (1867- 1893), eds. Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1992. [References to this volume will be designated by EP 1, followed by colon, page number.].
- Peirce, C.S. i. 1893-1913. The essential Peirce: Selected philosophical writing. Vol 2 (1893- 1913), ed. the Peirce Edition Project. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1998. [References to this volume will be designated by EP 2, followed by colon, page number.].
- Peirce, C.S. 1975. Charles Sanders Peirce: Contributions to "the Nation": Part I: 1869-1893, eds. Kenneth Laine Ketner and James Edward Cook, Lubbock: Texas Tech University Press.
- Peirce, C.S. 1978. Charles Sanders Peirce: Contributions to "the Nation": Part II: 1894-1900, eds. Kenneth Laine Ketner and James Edward Cook. Lubbock: Texas Tech University Press.
- Peirce, C.S. 1979. Charles Sanders Peirce: Contributions to "the Nation": Part III: 1901-1908, eds. Kenneth Laine Ketner and James Edward Cook. Lubbock: Texas Tech University Press.
- Peirce, C.S. 1987. Charles Sanders Peirce: Contributions to "the Nation": Part IV: Index, eds. Kenneth Laine Ketner and James Edward Cook. Lubbock: Texas Tech University Press.
- Peirce, C.S. 1877-1910. Illustrations of the logic of science, ed. C. de Waal. Chicago: Open Court [Cited as ILS p].
- Peirce, C.S. 2009. The logic of interdisciplinarity: The monist-series, ed. Elize Bisanz. Berlin: Akademie Verlag GmbH.
- Peirce, C.S. 1895-1908. Philosophy of mathematics: Selected writings, ed. M.E. Moore. Bloomington: Indiana University Press [Cited as PM p].
- Peirce, C.S. i. 1898. Reasoning and the logic of things: The Cambridge conferences lectures of 1898, ed. Kenneth Laine Ketner. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1992. [References to this volume will be designated by RLT, followed by lecture number, colon, page number.] Introduction, and comments, by Kenneth Laine Ketner and Hilary Putnam: 1992: 1-102.S. Peirce, Charles Sanders and Victoria Lady Welby. 2001. Semiotic and Significs: The Correspondence between Charles S. Peirce and Victoria, Lady Welby. Charles S. Hardwick, ed. with the assistance of James Cook, 2nd ed. The Press of Arisbe Associates.
- Ransdell, Joseph. 1992. Teleology and the autonomy of the semiosis process. In Signs of humanity/L'homme et ses signes, Vol 1, eds. Michel Balat, Janice Deledalle-Rhodes, and Gérard Deledalle, 239-258. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
- Short, Thomas. L. 1996. Interpreting Peirce's interpretant: A response to Lalor, Liszka, and Meyers. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 32(4): 488-541.
- Short, Thomas. L. 2004. The development of Peirce's theory of signs. In The Cambridge companion to Peirce, ed. Cheryl Misak, 214-240. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Short, Thomas. L. 2007a. Peirce's theory of signs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Short, Thomas. L. 2007b. Response. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 43(4): 663- 693.
- Stango, Marco. 2015. The pragmatic maxim and the normative sciences: Peirce's problematic "fourth" grade of clarity. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 51(1): 34-56.