Counterfactuals and Knowledge
Abstract
AI
AI
This paper explores the semantics of counterfactuals, particularly in the context of knowledge claims, drawing on the foundational works of Lewis, Stalnaker, and Kratzer. It critiques existing semantic frameworks that assume stable context-sensitivity in the evaluation of counterfactuals, discussing indeterminacy and conversational context variations that challenge traditional interpretations. The argument advocates for a contextualist approach to better account for the intricacies of knowledge claims reflected in counterfactual reasoning.
References (23)
- Brogaard, Berit & Joe Salerno. 2008. Counterfactuals and Context. Analysis 68(297). 39-46.
- DeRose, Keith. 1995. Solving the skeptical problem. Philosophical Review 104(1). 1-52.
- DeRose, Keith. 1999. Can It Be That It Would Have Been Even Though It Might Not Have Been? Noûs, Supplement: Philosophical Persepctives 33(13). 385-413.
- Emery, Nina. 2015. The Metaphysical Consequences of Counterfactual Skep- ticism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (Advanced online ac- cess: http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12254).
- von Fintel, Kai. 2001. Counterfactuals in a Dynamic Context. In Ken Hale: A Life in Language, MIT Press.
- Gillies, Thony. 2007. Counterfactual Scorekeeping. Linguistics and Philoso- phy 30. 329-360.
- 13 Moving to Ichikawa (2011)'s more sophisticated version of contextualism with basing doesn't help here. On this version, S knows that p just in case, for some evidence E, (i) S believes that p on the basis of E, and (ii) all E cases are p cases. (p.301) The counterexample need only be adjusted to include that Kristy believes that if the vase were to drop, it would break (or that the vase is fragile) based on some intuitively irrelevant or inconclusive evidence, e.g. that it is a vase. Since there are no drop&¬break-worlds in the domain, any evidence, no matter how irrelevant, will trivially eliminate any such worlds. 14 See Ichikawa (Forthcoming) for further discussion.
- Hájek, Alan. ms. Most Counterfactuals are False. ANU, monograph in progress.
- Hawthorne, John. 2004. Knowledge and Lotteries. Oxford University Press.
- Hawthorne, John. 2005. Chance and Counterfactuals. Philosophy and Phe- nomenological Research 70(2). 396-405.
- Ichikawa, Jonathan. 2011. Quantifiers, Knowledge, and Counterfactuals. Phi- losophy and Phenomenological Research LXXXII(2). 287-313.
- Ichikawa, Jonathan Jenkins. Forthcoming. Contextualizing Knowledge. Ox- ford University Press.
- Kratzer, Angelika. 1977. What 'must' and 'can' must and can mean. Lin- guistics and Philosophy 1(3). 337-355.
- Kratzer, Angelika. 1981. Partition and revision: The semantics of counter- factuals. Journal of Philosophical Logic 10(2). 201-216.
- Lewis, David. 1973. Counterfactuals. Blackwell.
- Lewis, David. 1986. Counterfactual Dependence and Time's Arrow. In Philo- sophical Papers Volume II, chap. 17. Oxford University Press.
- Lewis, Karen. 2016. Elusive Counterfactuals. Noûs 50(2). 286-313.
- Lewis, Karen. Forthcoming. Counterfactual Discourse in Context. Noûs .
- Moss, Sarah. 2012. On the Pragmatics of Counterfactuals. Noûs 46. 561-86.
- Moss, Sarah. 2013. Subjunctive Credences and Semantic Humility. Philoso- phy and Phenomenological Research LXXXVII(2). 251-278.
- Stalnaker, Robert. 1968. A Theory of Conditionals. In N. Rescher (ed.), Studies in logical theory, Oxford University Press.
- Stalnaker, Robert. 1981. A Defense of Conditional Excluded Middle. In Harper et al. (ed.), Ifs: Conditionals, Belief, Decision, Chance, and Time, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
- Williams, Robert G. 2008. Chances, Counterfactuals, and Similarity. Phi- losophy and Phenomenological Research 77(2). 385-420.