Notes on Quantum Mechanics and Consciousness
Sign up for access to the world's latest research
Abstract
There have lately been a variety of attempts to connect, or even explain, if not in fact, reduce human consciousness to quantum mechanical processes. Such attempts tend to draw a sharp and fundamental distinction between the role of consciousness in classical mechanics, and on the other hand, in quantum mechanics, with an insistence on the assumed exceptional character of the latter. What is strangely missed, however, is the role of human consciousness as such in the very discovery or creation of both of these physical theories. And this a priori role is far more important than all the possible a posteriori interplays between consciousness and the mentioned two theories of physics, interplays which may happen during one or another specific experiment, measurement, and so on. In this regard it is suggested that the specific features human consciousness may exhibit during interactions with quantum mechanical systems may as well have other explanations which do not appear to be less plausible, or less well founded.
Related papers
The relationship between quantum collapse and consciousness is reconsidered under the assumption that quantum collapse is an objective dynamical process. We argue that the conscious observer can have a distinct role from the physical measuring device during the process of quantum collapse owing to the intrinsic nature of consciousness; the conscious observer can know whether he is in a definite state or a quantum superposition of definite states, while the physical measuring device cannot “know”. As a result, the consciousness observer can distinguish the definite states and their quantum superposition, while the physical measuring device without consciousness cannot do. This provides a possible quantum physical method to distinguish man and machine. The new result also implies that consciousness has causal efficacies in the physical world when considering the existence of quantum collapse. Accordingly consciousness is not reducible or emergent, but a new fundamental property of matter. This may establish a quantum basis for panpsychism, and make it be a promising solution to the hard problem of consciousness. Furthermore, it is suggested that a unified theory of matter and consciousness includes two parts: one is the psychophysical principle or corresponding principle between conscious content and matter state, and the other is the complete quantum evolution of matter state, which includes the definite nonlinear evolution element introduced by consciousness and relating to conscious content. Lastly, some experimental schemes are presented to test the proposed quantum theory of consciousness.
2016
This paper explores the theme “quantum approaches to consciousness” by considering the work of one of the pioneers in the field. The physicist David Bohm (1917-1992) not only made important contrib ...
Journal of Consciousness Studies
The hard problem of consciousness is the problem of understanding how physical processes in the brain could give rise to conscious experience. In this paper, I suggest that in order to understand the relationship between consciousness and the physical world, we need to probe deeply into the nature of physical reality. This leads us to quantum physics and to a second explanatory gap: that between quantum and classical reality. I will seek a philosophical framework that can address these two gaps simultaneously. Our analysis of quantum mechanics will naturally lead us to the notion of a hidden reality and to the postulate that consciousness is an integral component of this reality. The framework proposed in the paper provides the philosophical underpinnings for a theory of consciousness while satisfactorily resolving the interpretation problem in quantum mechanics without the need to alter its mathematical structure. I also discuss some implications for a scientific theory of consciou...
2010
It has been suggested that consciousness plays an important role in quantum mechanics as it is necessary for the collapse of wave function during the measurement. Furthermore, this idea has spawned a symmetrical proposal: a possibility that quantum mechanics explains the emergence of consciousness in the brain. Here we formulated several predictions that follow from this hypothetical relationship and that can be empirically tested. Some of the experimental results that are already available suggest falsification of the first hypothesis. Thus, the suggested link between human consciousness and collapse of wave function does not seem viable. We discuss the constraints implied by the existing evidence on the role that the human observer may play for quantum mechanics and the role that quantum mechanics may play in the observer's consciousness.
Quantum and Consciousness Revisited, 2024
Annalen der Physik, 2011
It has been suggested that consciousness plays an important role in quantum mechanics as it is necessary for the collapse of wave function during the measurement. Here we formulated several predictions that follow from this hypothetical relationship and that can be empirically tested. Experimental results that are already available suggest falsification of these predictions. Thus, the suggested link between human consciousness and collapse of wave function does not seem viable. We discuss the implications of these conclusions on the role of the human observer for quantum mechanics and on the role of quantum mechanics for the observer's consciousness.
Quantum Consciousness: Exploring the Intersection of Mind and Physics, 2025
In the spirit of Erwin Schrödinger's What is Life?, I offer this work not as a definitive thesis, but as an earnest exploration across the boundaries of physics, neuroscience, and philosophy. For the present purpose, I beg to renounce any claim to authority and to be freed from the obligation such a claim would impose. My excuse is as follows: We have inherited from our intellectual ancestors a deep and enduring longing for unified, all-encompassing knowledge. The very word "university" reflects this aspiration-reminding us that, for centuries, the quest for universal understanding was seen as the highest aim of learning. Yet the explosion of knowledge over the past century has confronted us with a strange paradox: just as we begin to gather the pieces necessary to glimpse a more complete picture of reality, the sheer complexity and specialization of modern science makes it almost impossible for any single mind to hold it all together. I see no other escape from this dilemma-lest we forget the broader purpose of inquirythan for some of us to dare a synthesis of facts and theories, even if our knowledge of some elements is secondhand , incomplete, or imprecise, and even if doing so risks the appearance of folly. So much for my apology. This article is an attempt to weave together strands from quantum theory, consciousness studies, and metaphysics into a coherent, if speculative, perspective. It is a gesture toward unity-inviting open inquiry rather than proclaiming certainty. If I have strayed too far from the certainties of established science, it is not out of disregard, but from reverence-for the mystery itself. Consciousness, I suspect, will not yield its secrets to logic alone, nor to any one discipline. But in the act of reaching-across physics, philosophy, depth psychology, and poetry-we may glimpse something truer than proof: a resonance, a pattern, a hint of unity. And perhaps that is enough to continue the inquiry.
Here two viewpoints on quantum mechanics are reviewed: (a) it is purely formulas for calculations and predictions vs. (b) the formulas describe the behavior of real physical objects. What makes the latter a challenge to accept is such objects would not fall easily within the common paradigm of materialism-particles moved around by forces as governed by cause and effect. If it is accepted, also including consciousness in the quantum field becomes a relatively small addition that can help build quantum-neurological models of conscious experience.
PHILOSOPHY STUDY, 2020
Reality within the confines of philosophical speculation is a metaphysical conundrum. It can be viewed corporeally or incorporeally, mentally or extra-mentally or explained in general parlance naturally or supernaturally. The central matrix of this paper is to expose the melting point of the dichotomy between the seen and the unseen universe. It proposes that understanding consciousness and its relationship to quantum physics give a clear explanatory framework in comprehending the concept: reality. It posits further that man is basically consciousness expressed through theories observed in quantum physics. Quantum physics is the modern science that supports the theory of the unified field that everything in life is connected. It goes further to postulate that science, technology, and religion are subsumed in consciousness and quantum physics. The knowledge of interconnectedness of everything in the universe will expose us to the clear understanding that energy is the central matrix of reality and can be dissipated consciously or unconsciously to affect both mental and extra-mental realities. An awareness of this immanent nature within and around us will aid greater interaction and advancement in interdisciplinary studies that will improve the society.
ABSTRACT 46.07 Consciousness and the Quantum Field This paper is based in part on only four shreds of scientific evidence, the balance was developed from speculation and conjecture. ‡ In the context of this paper, “quantum field” refers to the realm of quanta, quantum activities, and the influences that affect quanta. Quanta. (plural, noun) What makes all of this interesting is to consider the bubble chamber evidence of the Higgs Bosom particle, which is also called the God particle, Adamantine particle, Ultimaton, and for myself the quantum particle. Quanta provide the self-organizing element to the Infinite Universe, including humans. Humans are self-organizing on two levels: survival of the species without conscious decision-making; and, the survival of the organized social existence of humanity requires conscious intention, decision-making, and action-implementation. We already have the capability to attain global peace, when it becomes important enough to use the innate tools that are embedded in the design of Homo sapiens. ##
Notes on Quantum Mechanics and Consciousness
Elemér E Rosinger
Department of Mathematics
University of Pretoria
Pretoria, 0002 South Africa
e-mail : eerosinger@hotmail.com
Abstract
There have lately been a variety of attempts to connect, or even explain, if not in fact, reduce human consciousness to quantum mechanical processes. Such attempts tend to draw a sharp and fundamental distinction between the role of consciousness in classical mechanics, and on the other hand, in quantum mechanics, with an insistence on the assumed exceptional character of the latter. What is strangely missed, however, is the role of human consciousness as such in the very discovery or creation of both of these physical theories. And this a priori role is far more important than all the possible a posteriori interplays between consciousness and the mentioned two theories of physics, interplays which may happen during one or another specific experiment, measurement, and so on. In this regard it is suggested that the specific features human consciousness may exhibit during interactions with quantum mechanical systems may as well have other explanations which do not appear to be less plausible, or less well founded.
1. Introduction
Since the literature on the relationship between consciousness and quantum processes is rather considerable, here for the sake of brevity, we shall refer specifically to one rather typical sample presented by the recent paper of Stapp.
For a start, let us for a moment take one or more steps back, and from the respective perspective, note a few features which may be relevant not only to the way one deals with the relationship between consciousness and quantum processes, but possibly as well to the venture of quantum mechanics itself.
A deficiency, which tends to amount to a rather regrettable feature of studies in quantum mechanics, is manifested in the fact that, subsequent to the times of John von Neumann ended in the 1950s, the main players prove, intentionally or not, to have a manifest disregard not only for the latest conquests of pure mathematics, but also of applied mathematics. What pure mathematics is concerned, this means a near unanimous limitation to concepts introduced and developed prior to World War II, such as Hilbert spaces, C∗-algebras, and the like, and of course, to the near exclusive use of the much earlier known scalars given by the usual real or complex numbers. On the other hand, when it comes to applied mathematics, one cannot but note with regret that by now classical, well established and massively used concepts are not employed according to their full relevance and power. For instance, we can mention in this regard linear and finite dimensional control theory, with concepts such as “state-space”, “observability”, “controlability”, “reachability”, “stability”, and so on, celebrated ever since the 1960s with their successes, among others, in the Kalman-Bucy filters.
It may appear to be a first natural reaction on the part of those involved in the cutting edge pursuit of quantum mechanics to disregard much of everything else in science. After all, it has always been a widely accepted assumption that, according to our best present knowledge and understanding, the quantum level is underlying all else in nature. Not to mention that quantum phenomena are so much different from whatever else we have known earlier.
However, two objections may nevertheless arise.
First, to the extent that in the study of quantum processes one goes outside of them and deals, for instance, with consciousness, mind, brain, or for that matter, with any other relevantly related macroscopic phenomenon, one may do well to be familiar with and make use of the state-of-the-art concepts in these non-quantum realms.
Second, scientific thinking can only benefit from what in more simple terms can be called cross-fertilization of concepts across a number of different ventures in science, often so different as at first not to appear being related in any relevant manner.
Another feature, ever since the 1920s, of the approaches of most of those involved in the cutting edge pursuit of quantum mechanics has been the relentless insistence on, and rather enthusiastic highlightening of what appeared as being the extraordinary and completely unprecedented difference between that theory, and on the other hand, all other earlier known theories of physics.
Such and other possibly questionable features in quantum mechanical studies have quite likely had their less than fortunate consequences.
Here in this paper we shall mean by quantum mechanics the theory of non-relativistic quantum systems of finitely many particles.
2. Are States of Quantum Systems of Any Relevance ?
In control theory, or more at large, in general systems theory, any given system S that is not supposed to be fixed in time is assigned a so called “state-space” XS which contains the set of all its different possible relevant manifestations.
In von Neumann’s first model of quantum mechanics, Rosinger [1, pp. 9-13], such a “state-space” is given by the vectors ψ of a suitable Hilbert space H, vectors which are called “wave functions”, and which are supposed to be normalized, that is, satisfy the condition ∥ψ∥=1. Further, in this model there is also the concept of “observable”, and it is given by self-adjoint operators A:H⟶H. Here however one should note a certain difference, when compared with the sense control theory uses the similarly named concept. Indeed, in quantum mechanics by “observable” one rather means a specific kind of “observation” or measurement of the quantum system, while in control theory, the term “observable” describes an important property of the system as a whole, and not of any of its particular observation or
measurement. One can recall in this regard the celebrated theorem of Kalman, according to which a finite dimensional linear system which is observable will also be stable, if and only if it is controllable.
Similarly, the concept of “state-space”, and that of “observable”, in its quantum specific sense, are present in von Neumann’s second model, Rosinger [1, pp. 9-13].
On the other hand, in spite of such a presence of the concept of “statespace”, one finds as a pillar of the Copenhagen Interpretation statements such as :
“The conception of objective reality of the elementary particles has thus evaporated not into the cloud of some obscure new reality concept but into the transparent clarity of a mathematics that represents no longer the behaviour of the particles but rather our knowledge of this behaviour”, Heisenberg.
In other words, the “state-space” is no longer supposed to incorporate anything at all related to the set of all different possible relevant manifestations of the quantum system which is under consideration. Instead, all that the “state-space” does - and is alleged to be able to do - is to incorporate but the different possible relevant manifestations of our knowledge of that quantum system.
Such a view obviously is a most remarkable - and in science, unprecedented - total renunciation of any possible ontological relation on our part to quantum systems, and implies the total resignation to a mere epistemological connection.
Nevertheless, the Copenhagen Interpretation does not deny that quantum system exists as such as physical entities, and that they may go through a variety of different physically relevant manifestations, and do so either all on their own, or in conjunction with their observation or measurement.
Those who may find such a total renunciation + total resignation hard to accept, among them Einstein, Schrödinger, or Bohm, may simply ask :
Are physicists, and for that matter, the theories of physics, ever to deal with the “state-spaces” of quantum systems in the physical sense of this concept, that is, as it is understood in all the other branches of physics, namely, ontologically?
And if not, then who else is supposed to do it?
And what kind of other possible scientific theories may be able to do so?
The Copenhagen Interpretation, instead of having a constructive approach to such questions, seems to take a special pride in the mentioned total renunciation + total resignation, and appears to do so under the pretext of, and in direct proportion to the truly unprecedented novelty in the whole of modern science of such a controversial position.
Naturally, scientists evermore and most eagerly aim at bringing forth truly unprecedented novelties. The Copenhagen Interpretation is obviously not a stranger to such an attitude. What is strange and unprecedented in science, however, about that interpretation is the eagerness to pay such a considerable price renunciation and resignation for trying to make sense out of the remarkable novelties of quantum phenomena.
3. What Aspect of Conscious Involvement Is More Important?
As far as we all know, humankind got to know about classical and quantum mechanics not as a gift from somewhere outside of itself, but as the discovery or creation of some of its own members. And needless to say, the respective processes of creation or discovery were acts of human consciousness.
By the way, lest we may overlook it, it is useful to recall that classical mechanics is by no means a closed or exhausted subject. Indeed, issues such as for instance turbulence in fluid flow, or even the existence of regular enough solutions of the Navier-Stokes equations, are still widely open and highly nontrivial problems.
In view of that one may consider that the involvement of human consciousness in classical or quantum mechanics not only starts with the discovery or creation of the respective physical theories, and keeps going on with their further development, but that such an “a priori” involvement is a far more deep and relevant manifestation of human consciousness within the realms of physics, than any other “a posteriori” conscious involvement during one or another specific physical experiment.
In a manifest contradistinction to the above, a great accent is often placed in the literature dealing with the relationship between consciousness and quantum processes on the significant difference the consciousness of the human observer plays in classical, as opposed to quantum mechanics.
It is for instance stated that in classical mechanics “… all physically described properties become completely determined by physically described properties alone, with consciousness a causally inert, or causally superfluous bystander. Correlations between the physically and psychologically described properties can be described within a classical physics based framework, but the psychologically described aspects will remain essentially epiphenomenal byproducts of brain activity”, Stapp.
When encountering such or similar views, and especially coming from partial or total supporters of the Copenhagen Interpretation, the following comment is hard to avoid :
The fact that classical mechanics, as correctly described in the above citation, is “causally complete” only shows that at the “a priori” stage of involvement in it of human consciousness - namely, of those who created or discovered it - a rather perfect job was accomplished. Consequently, in the “a posteriori” stages of involvement of consciousness, such as happens in the process of various experiments, human consciousness can have it so much easier, in particular, as a mere witness.
On the other hand, when it comes to quantum mechanics, if one starts with the mentioned total renunciation + total resignation promulgated by the Copenhagen Interpretation, and among others, replaces the
ontological “state-space” with a mere epistemological one, one clearly risks various forms “incompleteness” in the respective theory. After all, even the Copenhagen Interpretation does not go so far as to deny the physical existence of quantum system as ontological entities which go through a variety of different physically relevant manifestations. But then, by denying the very possibility of ever reaching in any theory that physical ontology, the risk is taken for “incompleteness”.
In this way, one may note that the attempts within the Copenhagen Interpretation which try to connect human consciousness with the dynamics of quantum systems are to a good extent trying to support themselves through a self-fabricated entrapment within the epistemic. Namely
- one first denies the very possibility of an ontological theory,
- then one ends up with incompleteness, and finally
- one has a chance to introduce some active, causal role for human consciousness during certain experimental processes, in an attempt to explain the whole range of dynamics of quantum systems.
4. About Relative Clumsiness
When one observes, for instance, the Moon from the Earth and does so with the naked eye, it is very hard to assume that one can cause by that any relevant disturbance in the motion of the Moon. In other words, such an experiment performed relating to the dynamics of the Moon can quite safely be considered as perfectly non-invasive in terms of that dynamics.
On the other hand, as it is well known, when we implement various experiments in genetic engineering, many of our actions end up being not only invasive, but simply destructive, even if they were not meant to be so.
The difference between the above two situations, both of them rather within the realms of classical mechanics, can be seen as a simple manifestation of “relative clumsiness” on our part, having much to do with the significant differences in the relative sizes we humans have, when compared with the respective objects of our interest.
Compared with the typical scales in the quantum realms, the relative difference between them and those of our human scales are far larger than when we compare ourselves with the realms of genes.
Consequently, it does not appear too far fetched to consider the possibility that various so far disregarded invasive effects may accompany many of the measurement and observation processes which, as usual, bring together in interaction macroscopic devices with quantum systems. And one of the consequences of such invasiveness may possibly be what goes under the name of the “collapse of the wave function”, which puts an instant end to the free dynamics of a quantum system as described by the Schrödinger equation, and switches it to some other state.
5. Is the Quantum World so Boringly Repetitive ?
One of the arguments brought by the Copenhagen Interpretation in support of the impossibility of an ontological quantum theory is what appears to be the inherent randomness of a variety of quantum phenomena, such as for instance, the radioactive decay.
As we know from a large variety of situations, randomness experienced on a certain level when dealing with a given physical process may not necessarily be the sign of an inherent essential aspect of the respective process. Indeed, sometime, like in the case of statistical mechanics, it may be the effect of an insufficient knowledge on our part of the precise initial state of the process. Or it may be a deeper ignorance, namely, of important aspects of the laws of dynamics of that physical process.
In the case of quantum systems, in addition to some consideration of
the possible effects of the above mentioned “clumsiness”, one should not disregard the eventuality that, because of the same reasons of immense discrepancies of the scales involved, we may miss on certain relevant features of quantum entities, thus exposing ourselves to what appear as random manifestations when seen on our level.
It is indeed most surprising to note the following rather dramatic discrepancy.
On our human scales, and higher up, till the cosmic ones, it is very hard, if not in fact impossible, to encounter among all the immensity of the number of objects we can observe two perfectly identical ones. On the other hand, on the atomic and on the quantum scales we make the assumption that, say, every two electrons are absolutely the same from whatever point of view relevant to physics.
Well, existence on the quantum or atomic scales must therefore be just about … infinitely boring …
Or perhaps, not …
In which case the various entities of the quantum realms may actually have features relevant physically, yet so far not known to us, and thus not taken into account.
Therefore, one possible way to see the randomness in a variety of quantum phenomena is as an effect of the combination of the “operative clumsiness”, mentioned in section 4 , with the “conceptual clumsiness” pointed to above, a clumsiness manifested in our present view of seeing existence on the quantum scales so endlessly boring due to the immense number of entities which are assumed to be perfectly identical from whatever physically relevant point of view …
Indeed, once the “conceptual clumsiness” of that “boringly repetitive” structure of the quantum realms is set aside, it is conceivable that, say for instance, electrons or photons do in fact spread across a considerable spectrum with respect to a number of yet not known physical features. And then, the randomness we may observe with respect to them may be the result of the statistical distribution of such features, features which in ways not yet known make electrons, photons, and so
on, behave somewhat differently during our operatively and conceptually clumsy present kind of experiments.
6. Let Us Have Some Mixture …
In Stapp, several recent proposals relating to a quantum theory of consciousness are mentioned. One of them is due to Hameroff & Penrose, in which three of the presently fascinating ideas are mixed together in a somewhat ad-hoc manner, in the hope of producing an effect in which the resulting whole may be larger than the sum of its parts. The respective parts are the celebrated Gödel incompleteness result of the early 1930s, the recent discovery of the microtubular structure of the neurons, and some ideas from the ongoing and still far from conclusive research related to quantum gravity.
A problem with such mixes of ideas is that, so often, they do not really fit together in order to form a more organic whole. What Hameroff & Penrose use in the hope of constituting a more genuine whole are some suggested estimates of typical time scales of the action of gravitation within the brain which, being of the order of tenth of a second, seem to correlate with those associated with conscious processes.
The validity and relevance of such estimates is, however, an open question, given that the possible actions of gravity on brain, mind, neurological processes, or thinking, let alone the respective more precise ways of manifestation, are still highly hypothetical.
7. The Alleged Dualism of Descartes
It is fashionable to label Descartes a “dualist”, or even “substance dualist”, Stapp. What is missed is a more thorough understanding of the world-views of thinkers in Europe of those times. To mention a few of them, Copernicus, Kepler, Galileo, Pascal, Descartes, Newton, Leibniz, or Spinoza were deeply religious men in the Judaeo-Christian tradition. Consequently, none of them - and this includes Descartes as well - could possibly be anything else but fervent “monists”.
As for “dualism”, or for that matter, “substance dualism”, chemistry is practicing it without any objections from any quarter, and it does so in a most successful manner, when it divides itself into its “inorganic” and “organic” branches.
Biology proceeds in a yet more dramatic manner, when it makes an essential differentiation between “living organisms” and all other forms of matter. And such a differentiation is by no means arbitrary or superficial. For instance, only plants are able to turn through their metabolism inorganic, thus clearly non-living matter, into living one. And by far most of the plants only use inorganic matter in their metabolic processes. Animals, on the other hand, must use in their metabolism mostly plants or other animals, since they cannot live only on inorganic intake.
As for Descartes, his division in “res cogitans” and “res extensa” was in his own view but of course about the two branches of a unique tree, two branches which grow out from the same one and only, universal and all encompassing, eternal grace of God’s act of creation. In this way, what is labelled as mere “dualism” is in the case of Descartes but about the two surface aspects of manifestation of the fundamental “monism” underlying, creating, and for evermore sustaining them.
In this regard, unless seen in ways similar with Descartes and his famous fellow thinkers of those older times, the so called “mind-body” or “brain-mind” problems are but problems of relating together two branches cut off a living tree, and with the tree lost, forgotten, or denied to exist, or even to have ever existed …
But as at the beginning of section 1 , let us stop again for a moment, and take one or more steps back, in order to gain some perspective. Indeed, we can use that typically human ability of consciousness which allows it to be self-referential.
And then we can ask the question :
When one thinks about solving a duality, like for instance, that of the “brain-mind” problem, is it not that such a
thinking happens under the aim of non-dualism, happens under the sign of an intended monism?
Therefore, either that unique tree from which the two terms of duality branched out has ever existed or not, we, by trying to solve the problem of that duality do in fact plant a tree, a unique tree in our own thinking, hoping that the two terms of duality may somehow be grafted into it in an organic manner …
This is, indeed, what we in fact do - consciously or not - when trying to go beyond any duality …
Here however, there seems to be quite some discrepancy between what the “… right hand and the left hand …” end up doing.
For instance, Stapp lists as the first main objection to dualism its failure to provide some understanding about the ways the two dual, and so essentially different, terms do interact. The second main objection, Stapp, is that, in the case of the “mind-body” problem, for instance, the physical description already gives a causally and deterministically complete account of what is going on. Thus the mental element of the duality is only left as a sort of “ghost in the machine”, with the physical side being perfectly able to get along all on its own.
The suggested solution, Stapp, of “quantum interactive dualism” is claimed to evade neatly both of these major objections. Namely, the interaction between the mental and physical is claimed to be given by the celebrated von Neumann account of the measurement process. The second main objection above is done away with due to the major and essential difference between classical, and on the other hand, quantum physical processes. Indeed, the latter ones - according to the Copenhagen Interpretation - are not causally complete, when taken all alone and only within themselves. And then it is precisely the mental processes which are alleged to come and complete the causal structure, and on top of that, they also underlie the structural relationship between the elements in our streams of conscious experiences.
What is missed in such and other similar arguments is that, before everything else, it is the unique, consistent, and persistent “tree” of
the thinking of the respective physicist concerned with such a duality which does hopefully bring together in an organic manner the two essentially different “branches”. And the “seed” of that “tree” is there - and must be there - already in the physicist’s thinking before one or another claimed method, such as for instance von Neumann’s measurement theory, is brought in to overcome duality.
Unfortunately however, to the extent that we may not be sufficiently aware of the typically human ability of self-referentiality of consciousness, we easily tend to miss on that “tree” in us … And we may also miss, Rosinger [2], on a far more fundamental “tree” …
References
[1] Hameroff, S R & Penrose, R : Orchestrated reduction of quantum coherence in brain microtubules : a model for consciousness. J. Consciousness Studies, Vol. 3, 1996, 36-53
[2] Heisenberg, W : The representation of nature in contemporary physics. Daedalus, Vol. 87, 1958, 95-108
[3] Rosinger, E E [1] : What is wrong with von Neumann’s theorem on “no hidden variables”. arXiv:quant-ph/0408191 v2
[4] Rosinger, E E [2] : Where and how does it happen ? arXiv:physics/0505041 v2
[5] Stapp, H : Quantum mechanical theories of consciousness (to appear in “Balckwell Companion to Cnsciousness”, 2005/6)
References (5)
- Hameroff, S R & Penrose, R : Orchestrated reduction of quantum coherence in brain microtubules : a model for consciousness. J. Consciousness Studies, Vol. 3, 1996, 36-53
- Heisenberg, W : The representation of nature in contemporary physics. Daedalus, Vol. 87, 1958, 95-108
- Rosinger, E E [1] : What is wrong with von Neumann's theorem on "no hidden variables". arXiv:quant-ph/0408191 v2
- Rosinger, E E [2] : Where and how does it happen ? arXiv:physics/0505041 v2
- Stapp, H : Quantum mechanical theories of consciousness (to ap- pear in "Balckwell Companion to Cnsciousness", 2005/6)