Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Outline

Rousseau and Republicanism

https://doi.org/10.1177/0090591715609101

Abstract

Rousseau was arguably one of the most important and influential of eighteenth-century republican thinkers. However, contemporary republican theorists, most notably Philip Pettit, have written him out of the republican canon by describing Rousseau as a “populist” rather than a republican. I argue that this miscasting of Rousseau is not just historically incorrect but that it has also led to a weakening of contemporary republican political theory. Rousseau was one of the few early modern republican thinkers to take seriously the problem of the tyranny of the majority and to attempt to formulate a cogent answer to that problem. Ignoring his contribution to republican political thought therefore cuts off contemporary republicans from an important resource for thinking about this problem.

FAQs

sparkles

AI

What factors contributed to Rousseau's exclusion from mainstream republicanism?add

Contemporary republican theorists, such as Philip Pettit, emphasize Rousseau's 'populist' notions as inconsistent with traditional republicanism. His association with the violent Jacobins in the 1790s and his paradoxical writing style also tarnished his reputation.

How does Rousseau address the problem of the tyranny of the majority?add

Rousseau posits that true governance requires reflecting the 'general will' versus mere majority opinion, ensuring decisions align with the public interest. This distinction is critical to maintaining freedom within a republican framework.

What makes Rousseau's view of government distinct from traditional republicans?add

Rousseau asserts that representative government contradicts republican ideals, advocating instead for direct participation in lawmaking. His later works, however, indicate a willingness to accept mechanisms of representation under strict conditions.

What role does patriotism play in Rousseau's political theory?add

Rousseau believes patriotism can foster civic virtue and solidarity in citizens, counteracting human egoism. He suggests equitable institutions can cultivate this sense of national belonging, essential for a functioning republic.

How does Rousseau's concept of collective decision-making differ from liberal perspectives?add

Unlike liberal thinkers who argue individual freedom requires limiting government power, Rousseau insists that freedom can coexist with laws made by the majority when those laws reflect common interests. His approach critiques the perception of majority rule as inherently tyrannical.

References (43)

  1. Democracy," American Political Science Review (2012) 106: 607-21. But that interpretation is incorrect to the extent that it entails that republicans understood the rule of law as being different from popular control. Both to historical and contemporary republicans, legal constraints can only be seen as compatible with freedom to the extent that they are made with the consent of (part of) the peo- ple.
  2. See Pettit, On the People's Terms, 153; and by the same author, "Law and Liberty," in Legal Republicanism: National and International Perspectives, ed. Samantha Besson and Jose Luis Marti (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 39-59;
  3. Marcia L. Colish, "The Idea of Liberty in Machiavelli," Journal of the History of Ideas 32 (1971): 323-50; Quentin Skinner, "The Republican Ideal of Political Liberty," in Machiavelli and Republicanism, ed. Gisela Bock, Quentin Skinner, and Maurizio Viroli (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 293-309.
  4. Algernon Sidney, Discourses Concerning Government by Algernon Sidney, Son to Robert Earl of Leicester, and Ambassador from the Commonwealth of England to Charles Gustavus King of Sweden, ed. John Toland (London, 1698), 8.
  5. Pettit, Republicanism, 27, 40.
  6. Richard Price, Observations on the Nature of Civil Liberty, the Principles of Government, and the Justice and Policy of the War with America. To which is added, an Appendix and Postscript, containing, a State of the National Debt, an Estimate of the Money drawn from the Public by the Taxes, and an Account of the National Income and Expenditure since the last War. The 9th edition. (London: Edward and Charles Dilly and Thomas Cadell, 1776), 46.
  7. Ibid., 6.
  8. Ibid., 7.
  9. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Discourses and Other Early Political Writings, ed. and trans. Victor Gourevitch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 176-78. As Robert Wokler also remarks, to Rousseau freedom meant first and foremost "the absence of personal dependence or domination." Wokler, Rousseau, the Age of Enlightenment and Their Legacies, ed. Bryan Garsten, with an introduction by Christopher Brooke (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2012), 178.
  10. Rousseau, The Discourses, 115.
  11. Jean-Jaques Rousseau, The Social Contract and Other Later Political Writings, ed. and trans. Victor Gourevitch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 49-50.
  12. Pettit, On the People's Terms, 15.
  13. Rousseau, The Social Contract, 201. Helena Rosenblatt has moreover argued that Rousseau's rejection of representative government in the Social Contract can be understood as a matter of political expediency and, more specifically, as an attack on elitist conceptions of representation embraced by the Genevan patri- ciate.
  14. See Helena Rosenblatt, Rousseau and Geneva: From the First Discourse to the Social Contract, 1749-1762 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 247-50.
  15. Price, Observations on the Nature of Liberty, 7-8.
  16. Pettit, "Two Republican Traditions," 184-88.
  17. Rousseau, The Social Contract, 99.
  18. Ibid., 95.
  19. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Political Writings, ed. C. E. Vaughan (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1962), vol. 1, 240.
  20. For a contrary argument, see Pettit, On the People's Terms, 213.
  21. John Stuart Mill, On Liberty with The Subjection of Women and Chapters on Socialism, ed. Stefan Collini (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 7-8.
  22. Ibid., 8. For a similar argument about the liberal rejection of the republican that majority rule is unproblematic as long as the decision-making process is sufficiently deliberative: "Policies that are not neutral may not be illegitimately oppressive of minorities if these have been the subject of extensive delibera- tion at different levels, if all voices have had opportunity to receive a hearing, to accommodate the deep concerns of all citizens equally, if certain provisions are made for cases of permanent minorities. Honohan, Civic Republicanism, 248-49.
  23. David Miller, "Republicanism, National Identity and Europe," in Laborde and John Maynor, eds., Republicanism and Political Theory, 140.
  24. Rousseau, The Social Contract, 124.
  25. Ibid.
  26. For a good account of Rousseau's concept of the general will from a contem- porary analytical-philosophical perspective, see Joshua Cohen, Rousseau: A Free Community of Equals (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 60-96.
  27. However, note that this interpretation is not shared by all Rousseau scholars. For a very different, influential interpretation emphasizing a more rationalistic understanding of the general will, see Patrick Riley, "A Possible Explanation of Rousseau's General Will," The American Political Science Review 64 (1970): 86-97. In his important contribution to this debate, Christopher Bertram has argued that Rousseau's notion of the general will can be understood in both a democratic and a more rationalistic, transcendental way. However, Bertram concludes that a textual analysis of the Social Contract offers more support for the democratic reading. See Christopher Bertram, "Rousseau's Legacy in Two Conceptions of the General Will: Democratic and Transcendent," The Review of Politics 74 (2012): 403-19.
  28. Rousseau, The Social Contract, 53.
  29. This criticism goes back to at least the 1950s, when it was famously articu- lated by Jacob Talmon in his attack on Rousseau, The Origins of Totalitarian Democracy (Secker & Warburg, 1952). For a more recent articulation, see for instance: Lester Crocker, "Rousseau's Soi-Disant Liberty," in Rousseau and Liberty, ed. Robert Wokler (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1995), 244-66; and Stanley Hoffman, "The Social Contract, or the Mirage of the General Will," in Rousseau and Freedom, ed. Christie McDonald and Stanley Hoffman (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 119.
  30. Arthur Melzer, The Natural Goodness of Man: On the System of Rousseau's Thought (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), 154.
  31. On this issue, see Ethan Putterman, Rousseau, Law and the Sovereignty of the People (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 27-29. But com- pare John McCormick, "Rousseau's Rome and the Repudiation of Populist Republicanism," Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy (CRISPP) 10 (2007): 3-27. McCormick argues that Rousseau can be read as a defender of timocracy, rather than of popular rule. For counterarguments, see Putterman, Rousseau, 90-95.
  32. Rousseau, The Social Contract, 8.
  33. Ibid., 60. 40. This reading of Rousseau as a precursor of Condorcet's goes back to Brian Barry's Political Argument (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1965), 292-94. It was later elaborated by Bernard Grofman and Scott Feld in their important paper "Rousseau's General Will: A Condorcetian Perspective," American Political Science Review 82 (1988): 567-76. Note that Melissa Schwartzberg has recently argued that Rousseau's arguments for majority rule were not just based on epis- temic reasons, but that moral considerations also played an important role. See Schwartzberg, "Voting the General Will: Rousseau on Decision Rules," Political Theory 36 (2008): 403-23.
  34. Christian List and Robert Goodin, "Epistemic Democracy: Generalizing the Condorcet Jury Theorem," The Journal of Political Philosophy 9 (2001): 24. For a strong defense of the epistemic value democracy, relying, among other argu- ments, on Condorcet's jury theorem, see also Hélène Landemore, Democratic Reason: Politics, Collective Intelligence and the Rule of the Many (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2012). Of course, Rousseau's and Condorcet's defense of the epistemic value of democracy depends on certain preconditions: that voters are sufficiently informed about the question at hand, that they are willing to vote in the public interest rather than in their own interest, and that the decision-making process is not affected by "factions" or organized interest groups. These conditions are of course difficult to meet in the real world, as it has been pointed out, for instance, by Jason Brennan, "How Smart Is Democracy? You Can't Answer That a Priori," Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 26 (2014): 33-58.
  35. For a recent articulation of this view, see Cohen, Rousseau, 98; and Alan Ryan, On Politics: A History of Political Thought: From Herodotus to the Present (New York: Liveright, 2012), 571-72.
  36. Rousseau, The Social Contract, 16.
  37. For a good overview of the debate about the ethical implications of patrio- tism, see Igor Primoratz, "Patriotism and Morality: Mapping the Terrain," in Patriotism: Philosophical and Political Perspectives, ed. Igor Primoratz and Aleksandar Pavkovic (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2007), 17-36.
  38. E.g., William Connolly, Pluralism (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2005), 136.
  39. Rousseau, Social Contract, 179-93.
  40. Ibid., 18.
  41. Jürgen Habermas, "On the Relation between the Nation, the Rule of Law, and Democracy," in The Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory, ed. Ciaran Cronin and Pablo De Greif (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1998).
  42. See especially Margaret Canovan, "Patriotism Is Not Enough," British Journal of Political Science 30 (2000): 413-32.
  43. Bo Rothstein and Dietlind Stolle, "The State and Social Capital: An Institutional Theory of Generalized Trust," Comparative Politics 40 (2008): 441-59.