Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Outline

Induction Science and Morality

2025, Springer

Abstract

I attempt to refute Hume's problem of induction. I raise the problem of counter-induction. I develop a template for generating philosophical problems. I develop and defend stage theory of scientific development for scientific realism. I develop and defend two new metaethical theories: cultural emotivism and moral functionalism. I argue that to compare morality to mathematics is to lose credibility. I develop the problem of moral induction against moral realism.

References (281)

  1. de Ray, C. (2022). A new epistemological case for theism. Religious Studies, 58(2), 379-400.
  2. Goldman, A. and Beddor, B. (2021). Reliabilist epistemology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/reliabilism/>.
  3. Hume, D. (1993). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
  4. Lee, B. (2022). A coherentist justification of induction. Erkenntnis, 87(1), 35-52.
  5. Norton, J. (2003). A material theory of induction. Philosophy of Science, 70(4), 647-670.
  6. Park, S. (2015). Explanatory failures of relative realism. Epistemologia, 38(1), 16-28.
  7. Park, S. (2017). The uniformity principle vs. the disuniformity principle. Acta Analytica, 32(2), 213-222.
  8. Park, S. (2018). The anti-induction for scientific realism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 95(3), References
  9. Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  10. de Ray, C. (2022a). A new epistemological case for theism. Religious Studies, 58(2), 379-400.
  11. Fine, A. (1991). Piecemeal realism. Philosophical Studies, 61(1-2), 79-96.
  12. Goldman, A. (1979). What is justified belief? In G. S. Pappas (Ed.), Justification and knowledge: New studies in epistemology (pp. 1-23). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
  13. Goldman, A. and Beddor, B. (2021). Reliabilist epistemology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/reliabilism/>.
  14. Hume, D. (1993). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
  15. Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48(1), 19-49.
  16. Laudan, L. (1984). Explaining the success of science: Beyond epistemic realism and relativism.
  17. In J. Cushing, C. Delaney, and G. Gutting (Eds.), Science and reality (pp. 83-105). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
  18. Lee, B. (2022). A coherentist justification of induction. Erkenntnis, 87(1), 35-52.
  19. Lehrer, K., (2000). Theory of knowledge, Boulder: Westview Press.
  20. Mizrahi, M. (2013). The argument from underconsideration and relative realism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 27(4), 393-407.
  21. Park, S. (2015). Explanatory failures of relative realism. Epistemologia, 38(1), 16-28.
  22. Park, S. (2017). The uniformity principle vs. the disuniformity principle. Acta Analytica, 32(2), 213-222.
  23. Park, S. (2018). The anti-induction for scientific realism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 95(3), 329-342.
  24. Park, S. (2023). Inference to the best explanation, naturalism, and theism. Implicit Religion, 472-485.
  25. Park, S. (2022). Embracing scientific realism. Cham: Springer.
  26. Sellars, W. (1963). Science, perception and reality. Atascadero: Ridgeview.
  27. Sellars, W. (1979). Essays in philosophy and its history. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
  28. van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  29. van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  30. Weintraub, R. (2013). Induction and inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Studies, 166(1), 203-216.
  31. Wray, B. (2008). The argument from underconsideration as grounds for anti-realism: A defence. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 22(3), 317-326.
  32. Hume, D. (1993). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
  33. Norton, J. (2003). A material theory of induction. Philosophy of Science, 70(4), 647-670.
  34. Park, S. (2017). The uniformity principle vs. the disuniformity Principle. Acta Analytica, 32(2), 213-222.
  35. Park, S. (2018). The anti-induction for scientific realism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 95(3), 329-342.
  36. Park, S. (2022). Embracing scientific realism. Cham: Springer.
  37. Salmon, W. (1957). Should we attempt to justify induction? Philosophical Studies, 8(3), 33- 48. References
  38. Alai, M. (2017). Resisting the historical objections to realism: Is Doppelt's a viable solution? Synthese, 194(9), 3267-3290.
  39. de Ray, C. (2022). A new epistemological case for theism. Religious Studies, 58(2), 379-400.
  40. Fahrbach, L. (2011a). How the growth of science ends theory change. Synthese, 180(2), 139- 155.
  41. Fahrbach, L. (2011b). Theory change and degrees of success. Philosophy of Science, 78(5), 1283-1292.
  42. Hempel, C. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
  43. Mizrahi, M. (2013). The pessimistic induction: A bad argument gone too far. Synthese, 190(15), 3209-3226.
  44. Mizrahi, M. (2020). The relativity of theory: Key positions and arguments in the contemporary scientific realism/antirealism debate. Cham: Springer.
  45. Müller, F. (2015). The pessimistic meta-induction: Obsolete through scientific progress? International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 29(4), 393-412.
  46. Park, S. (2011). A confutation of the pessimistic induction. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 42(1), 75-84.
  47. Park, S. (2017). Scientific antirealists have set fire to their own houses. Prolegomena, 16(1), 23-37.
  48. Park, S. (2019). The disastrous implications of the 'English' view of rationality in a social world. Social Epistemology, 33(1), 88-99.
  49. Park, S. (2023). Inference to the best explanation, naturalism, and theism. Implicit Religion, 472-485.
  50. Psillos, S. (2018). Realism and theory change in science. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. In E. N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/realism-theory-change/>.
  51. van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  52. van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  53. Weintraub, R. (2013). Induction and inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Studies, 166(1), 203-216.
  54. Wray, K. (2021). Induction, rationality, and the realism/antirealism debate: A reply to Shech. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science. 34(4), 243-247.
  55. de Ray, C. (2022). A new epistemological case for theism. Religious Studies, 58(2), 379-400.
  56. Hume, D. (1993). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
  57. Lehrer, K., (2000). Theory of knowledge, Boulder: Westview Press.
  58. Park, S. (2017). The uniformity principle vs. the disuniformity principle. Acta Analytica, 32(2), 213-222.
  59. Park, S. (2018). The anti-induction for scientific realism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 95(3), 329-342.
  60. Park, S. (2021). On the argument from double spaces: A Reply to Moti Mizrahi. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective, 10(2), 1-6.
  61. Park, S. (2022). Embracing scientific realism. Cham: Springer.
  62. van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  63. Weintraub, R. (2013). Induction and inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Studies, 166(1), 203-216.
  64. Hume, D. (1993). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
  65. Ladyman, J., Douven, I., Horsten, L., and van Fraassen, B. (1997). A defense of van Fraassen's critique of abductive inference: Reply to Psillos. The Philosophical Quarterly, 47(188), 305- 321.
  66. Magnus, P.D. and Callender, C. (2004). Realist ennui and the base rate fallacy. Philosophy of Science, 71(3). 320-338.
  67. Norton, J. (2003). A material theory of induction. Philosophy of Science, 70(4), 647-670.
  68. Park, S. (2017). Understanding without justification and belief? Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology, 21(3), 379-389.
  69. Park, S. (2022a). Embracing scientific realism. Cham: Springer.
  70. Park, S. (2022b). The contextual theory of explanation and inference to the best explanation. Axiomathes, 32(S2), 311-326.
  71. Shech, E. (2021). Darwinian-selectionist explanation, radical theory change, and the observable-unobservable dichotomy. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 34(4), 221-241.
  72. van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  73. van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  74. van Fraassen, B. C. (2007). From a view of science to a new empiricism. In B. Monton (Ed.), Images of empiricism: Essays on science and stances, with a reply from Bas C. van Fraassen, (pp. 337-383). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  75. van Fraassen, B. (2017). Misdirection and misconception in the scientific realism debates. In E. Agazzi (Ed.), Varieties of scientific realism: Objectivity and truth in science (pp. 95-108). Cham: Springer.
  76. Wray, B. (2012). Epistemic privilege and the success of science. Noûs, 46(3), 375-385.
  77. Wray, K. (2018). Resisting scientific realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  78. Wray, K. (2021). Induction, rationality, and the realism/antirealism debate: A reply to Shech. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 34(4), 243-247. References
  79. Alai, M. (2017). Resisting the historical objections to realism: Is Doppelt's a viable solution? Synthese, 194(9), 3267-3290.
  80. Alvaro, Carlo (2021). Atheism as an extreme rejection of rational evidence for the existence of God. The Heythrop Journal, 62(2), 1-16.
  81. Chakravartty, A. (2008). What you don't know can't hurt you: Realism and the unconceived. Philosophical Studies, 137(1), 149-158.
  82. Chang, H. (2011). The persistence of epistemic objects through scientific change. Erkenntnis, 75(3), 413-429.
  83. Frost-Arnold, G. (2011). From the pessimistic induction to semantic antirealism. Philosophy of Science, 78(5), 1131-1142.
  84. Frost-Arnold, G. (2019). How to be a historically motivated antirealist: The problem of misleading evidence. Philosophy of Science, 86(5), 906-917.
  85. Graham, D. (2013). Science before Socrates: Parmenides, Anaxagoras, and the new astronomy. New York: Oxford University Press.
  86. Harker, D. (2015). Creating scientific controversies: Uncertainty and bias in science and society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  87. Harrison, P. (2015). The territories of science and religion. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  88. Hempel, C. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall.
  89. Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. Berkeley: University of California Press.
  90. Leplin, J. (1997). A novel defense of scientific realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
  91. Lipton, P. (2005). The truth about science. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 360, 1259-1269.
  92. Mizrahi, M. (2016). The history of science as a graveyard of theories: A philosophers' myth. International Studies in Philosophy of Science, 30(3), 263-278.
  93. Müller, F. (2015). The pessimistic meta-induction: Obsolete through scientific progress? International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 29(4), 393-412.
  94. Musgrave, A. (1985). Realism vs. constructive empiricism. In P. Churchland & C. Hooker (Eds.), Images of science: Essays on realism and empiricism. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
  95. Park, S. (2016). Refutations of the two pessimistic inductions. Philosophia, 44(3), 835-844.
  96. Park, S. (2017). The uniformity principle vs. the disuniformity principle. Acta Analytica, 32(2), 213-222.
  97. Park, S. (2018a). The anti-induction for scientific realism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 95(3), 329-342.
  98. Park, S. (2018b). The grand pessimistic induction. Review of Contemporary Philosophy, 17, 7-19.
  99. Park, S. (2019a). The absolute and relative pessimistic inductions. Problemos, 95: 94-104.
  100. Park, S. (2019b). How to formulate scientific realism and antirealism. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 50(4), 477-488.
  101. Park, S. (2022). Embracing scientific realism. Cham: Springer.
  102. Ruhmkorff, S. (2011). "Some Difficulties for the Problem of Unconceived Alternatives", Philosophy of Science 78 (5): 875-886.
  103. Ruhmkorff, S. (2013). Global and local pessimistic meta-inductions. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 27(4), 409-428.
  104. Sorensen, R. (2013). Veridical idealizations. In M. Frappier, L. Meynell, and J. Brown, (Eds.), Thought experiments in philosophy, science, and the arts. (pp. 30-52). New York: Routledge.
  105. Stanford, K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  106. Stengers, I. (2000). The invention of modern science. D. Smith (Trans.), Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
  107. van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  108. van Fraassen, B. (2007). Reply: From a view of science to a new empiricism. In B. Monton (Ed.), Images of empiricism: Essays on science and stances, with a reply from Bas van Fraassen (pp. 337-383). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  109. van Fraassen, B. (2017). Misdirection and misconception in the scientific realism debates. In E. Agazzi (Ed.), Varieties of scientific realism: Objectivity and truth in science (pp. 95-108). Cham: Springer.
  110. Bird, A. (2007). What is scientific progress? Noûs 41(1), 64-89.
  111. Bird, A. (2018). Thomas Kuhn. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/thomas-kuhn/>.
  112. Boyd, R. (1980). Scientific realism and naturalistic epistemology. PSA Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association, 1980(2), 613-662.
  113. Fahrbach, L. (2011a). How the growth of science ends theory change. Synthese, 180(2), 139- 155.
  114. Fahrbach, L. (2011b). Theory change and degrees of success. Philosophy of Science, 78(5), 1283-1292.
  115. Frost-Arnold, G. (2019). How to be a historically motivated antirealist: The problem of misleading evidence. Philosophy of Science, 86(5), 906-917.
  116. Kuhn, T. (1962/1970). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  117. Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. Berkeley: University of California Press.
  118. Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48(1), 19-49.
  119. Leplin, J. (1997). A novel defense of scientific realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
  120. Lyons, T. (2005). Toward a purely axiological scientific realism. Erkenntnis, 63(2), 167-204.
  121. Mizrahi, M. (2013). The pessimistic induction: A bad argument gone too far. Synthese, 190(15), 3209-3226.
  122. Mizrahi, M. (2015). Historical inductions: New cherries, same old cherry-picking, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2), 129-148.
  123. Mizrahi, M. (2016). The history of science as a graveyard of theories: A philosophers' myth. International Studies in Philosophy of Science, 30(3), 263-278.
  124. Musgrave, A. (1985). Realism vs. constructive empiricism. In P. Churchland & C. Hooker (Eds.), Images of science: Essays on realism and empiricism. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
  125. Park, S. (2011). A confutation of the pessimistic induction. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 42(1), 75-84.
  126. Park, S. (2017). The uniformity principle vs. the disuniformity principle. Acta Analytica, 32(2), 213-222.
  127. Park, S. (2018a). The grand pessimistic induction. Review of Contemporary Philosophy, 17: 7-19.
  128. Park, S. (2018b). The anti-induction for scientific realism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 95(3), 329-342.
  129. Park, S. (2019). New objections to the problem of unconceived alternatives. Filosofia Unisinos, 20(2), 138-145.
  130. Poincaré, H. (1905/1952). Science and hypothesis. New York: Dover.
  131. Stanford, K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  132. van Fraassen, Bas (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press. References
  133. Akins, K. (1996). Of sensory systems and the 'aboutness' of mental states. Journal of Philosophy, 93(3), 337-372.
  134. Darwin, C., & Darwin, F. (1888). The life and letters of Charles Darwin. London: John Murray.
  135. De Cruz, H., Boudry, M., De Smedt, J., Blancke, S. (2011). Evolutionary Approaches to Epistemic Justification. Dialectica, 65(4), 517-535.
  136. de Ray, C. (2022). An evolutionary skeptical challenge to scientific realism. Erkenntnis, 87(2), 969-989.
  137. Friedman, M. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. The Journal of Philosophy, 71: 5-19.
  138. Goldman, A. and Beddor, B. (2021). Reliabilist epistemology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/reliabilism/>.
  139. Hempel, C. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
  140. Kuhn, T. (1962/1970). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  141. Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. California: University of California Press.
  142. Lipton, P. (2003). Inference to the best explanation. London: Routledge.
  143. Park, S. (2017). Problems with using evolutionary theory in philosophy. Axiomathes, 27(3), 321-332.
  144. Park, S. (2022). The realist and selectionist explanations for the success of science. Synthese, 200(233). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03703-0
  145. Putnam, H. (1975). Mathematics, matter and method: Philosophical papers, volume 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  146. Salmon, W. (1978). Why ask, "Why?"? An inquiry concerning scientific explanation. In J. Kourany (Ed.), Scientific knowledge: Basic issues in the philosophy of science. CA: Wadsworth Publishing Company.
  147. Stanford, K. (2006). Exceeding our Grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  148. Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109-166.
  149. Alai, M. (2017). Resisting the historical objections to realism: Is Doppelt's a viable solution? Synthese, 194(9), 3267-3290.
  150. Alvaro, C. (2020). The incoherence of moral relativism. Cultura: International Journal of Philosophy of Culture and Axiology, 17(1), 19-38.
  151. Baker, A. (2005). Are there genuine mathematical explanations of physical phenomena? Mind, 114(454), 223-237.
  152. Blackburn, S. (1993). Essays in quasi-realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
  153. Fine, A. (1991). Piecemeal realism. Philosophical Studies, 61(1-2), 79-96.
  154. Hare, R. (1952). Language of morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  155. Harman, G. (1996). Moral relativism. In S. Satris (Ed.) (2008). Taking sides: Clashing views on moral issues. 11th ed. Mcgraw-Hill/Dushkin.
  156. Hume, D. (1978). A treatise of human nature. In L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch (Eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  157. Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science: Science without legend, objectivity without illusions. New York: Oxford University Press.
  158. Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. California: University of California Press.
  159. Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48(1), 19-49.
  160. Leplin, J. (1997). A novel defense of scientific realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
  161. Mackie, J. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin Books.
  162. Mizrahi, M. (2013). The pessimistic induction: A bad argument gone too far. Synthese, 190(15), 3209-3226.
  163. Mizrahi, M. (2015). Historical inductions: New cherries, same old cherry-picking. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 29(2), 129-148.
  164. Mizrahi, M. (2016). The history of science as a graveyard of theories: A philosophers' myth. International Studies in Philosophy of Science, 30(3), 263-278.
  165. Mizrahi, M. (2020). The relativity of theory: Key positions and arguments in the contemporary scientific realism/antirealism debate. Cham: Springer.
  166. Musgrave, A. (1985). Realism vs. constructive empiricism. In P. Churchland and C. Hooker (Eds.), Images of science: Essays on realism and empiricism (pp. 197-221). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  167. Musgrave, A. (1988). The ultimate argument for scientific realism. In R. Nola (Ed.), Relativism and realism in science (pp. 229-252). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  168. Park, S. (2009). Philosophical responses to underdetermination in science. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 40(1), 115-124.
  169. Park, S. (2011a). Coherence of our best scientific theories. Foundations of Science, 16(1), 21- 30.
  170. Park, S. (2011b). Defence of cultural relativism. Cultura. International Journal of Philosophy of Culture and Axiology, 8(1), 159-170.
  171. Park, S. (2011c). A confutation of the pessimistic induction. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 42(1), 75-84.
  172. Park, S. (2012). Against moral truths. Cultura: International Journal of Philosophy of Culture and Axiology, 9(1), 179-194.
  173. Park, S. (2014). A pessimistic induction against scientific antirealism. Organon F, 21(1), 3-21.
  174. Park, S. (2017). Moral vegetarianism vs. moral omnivorism. Human Affairs, 27(3), 289-300.
  175. Park, S. (2018). The anti-induction for scientific realism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 95(3), 329-342.
  176. Park, S. (2019). The coherence of evolutionary theory with its neighboring theories. Acta Biotheoretica, 67(2), 87-102.
  177. Park, S. (2022a). Embracing scientific realism. Cham: Springer.
  178. Park, S. (2022b). Moral subjectivism vs. moral objectivism. Filosofija. Sociologija, 33(3), 269-276.
  179. Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. New York: Routledge.
  180. Putnam, H. (1975). Mathematics, matter and method: Philosophical papers, volume 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  181. Putnam, H. (1979). Mathematics, matter and method: Philosophical papers, volume 1. 2 nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  182. Quine, W. (1980). From a logical point of view. 2 nd ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  183. Saatsi, J. (2009). Grasping at realist straws. Metascience, 18(3), 355-362.
  184. Singer, P. (2009). Animal liberation: The definitive classic of the animal movement. New York: HarperCollins Publisher.
  185. Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.
  186. Stanford, K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  187. Stevenson, C. (1944). Ethics and language. New Haven: Yale University Press.
  188. Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109-166.
  189. van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  190. Wray, B. (2013). Pessimistic induction and the exponential growth of science reassessed. Synthese, 190(18), 4321-4330.
  191. Williams, E. (2015). The possibility of an ongoing moral catastrophe. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 18(5), 971-982.
  192. Blackburn, S. (1993). Essays in quasi-realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
  193. Bourget, D. and Chalmers, D. (2014). What do philosophers believe? Philosophical Studies, 170(3), 465-500.
  194. Estes, W. (1986). Array models for category learning. Cognitive Psychology, 18(4), 500-549.
  195. Goldman, A. (1993). The psychology of folk psychology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 16(1), 15-28.
  196. Goldman, A. and Beddor, B. (2021). Reliabilist epistemology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/reliabilism/>.
  197. Hare, R. (1952). Language of morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  198. Huemer, M. (2016). A liberal realist answer to debunking skeptics: the empirical case for realism. Philosophical Studies, 173(7), 1983-2010.
  199. Mackie, J. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin Books.
  200. Maxwell, G. (1962). The ontological status of theoretical entities. In H. Feigl and G. Maxwell (Eds.), Scientific explanation, space, and time: Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (pp. 181-192). Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press.
  201. Park, S. (2012). Against moral truths. Cultura: International Journal of Philosophy of Culture and Axiology, 9(1), 179-194.
  202. Schick, T. Jr. and Vaughn, L. (2010). Doing philosophy: An introduction through thought experiments. New York, NY: The McGraw-Hill Companies.
  203. Stevenson, C. (1944). Ethics and language. New Haven: Yale University Press.
  204. Stich, S. (1993). Moral philosophy and mental representation. In M. Hechter, L. Nadel, and R. Michod (Eds.), The origin of values (215-228). Hawthorne, New York: Walter de Gruyter.
  205. Stich, S. (2019). The quest for the boundaries of morality. In A. Zimmerman, K. Jones and M. Timmons (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of moral epistemology (15-37). New York: Routledge.
  206. Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109-166.
  207. Baker, A. (2005). Are there genuine mathematical explanations of physical phenomena? Mind, 114(454), 223-237.
  208. Baker, A. (2009). Mathematical explanation in science. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60(3), 611-633.
  209. Balaguer, M. (2018). Fictionalism in the philosophy of mathematics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/fictionalism-mathematics/>.
  210. Bourget, D. and Chalmers, D. (2014). What do philosophers believe? Philosophical Studies, 170(3), 465-500.
  211. DeLapp, K. (2023). Metaethics. The Internet encyclopedia of philosophy. https://iep.utm.edu/metaethi/
  212. Estes, W. (1986). Array models for category learning. Cognitive Psychology, 18(4), 500-549.
  213. Huemer, M. (2016). A liberal realist answer to debunking skeptics: the empirical case for realism. Philosophical Studies, 173(7), 1983-2010.
  214. Jones, T. (1970). The classical mind: A history of Western philosophy. Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich College Publishers.
  215. Hume, D. (1978). A treatise of human nature. In L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch (Eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  216. Kim, S. (2023). Moral realism. The internet encyclopedia of philosophy. https://iep.utm.edu/moralrea/
  217. Mackie, J. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin Books.
  218. Park, S. (2003). Ontological order in scientific explanation. Philosophical Papers, 32(2), 157- 170.
  219. Park, S. (2017). In defense of mathematical inferentialism. Analysis and Metaphysics, 16, 70- 83. Park, S. (2022a). Embracing scientific realism. Cham: Springer.
  220. Park, S. (2022b). Moral subjectivism vs. moral objectivism. Filosofija. Sociologija, 33, 191- 198. Putnam, H. (1971). Philosophy of logic. New York: Harper and Row.
  221. Quine, W. (1948). On what there is. Review of Metaphysics, 2(5), 21-38.
  222. Baker, A. (2005). Are there genuine mathematical explanations of physical phenomena? Mind, 114(454), 223-237.
  223. Baker, A. (2009). Mathematical explanation in science. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60(3), 611-633.
  224. Blackburn, S. (1993). Essays in quasi-realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
  225. Chagnon, N. (1988). Life histories, blood revenge, and warfare in a tribal population. Science, 239(4843), 985-992.
  226. Friedman, M. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. The Journal of Philosophy, 71: 5-19.
  227. Hare, R. (1952). Language of morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  228. Hempel, C. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
  229. Huemer, M. (2016). A liberal realist answer to debunking skeptics: the empirical case for realism. Philosophical Studies, 173(7), 1983-2010.
  230. Kitcher, P. (1981). Explanatory unification. Philosophy of Science, 48(4), 507-531.
  231. Mackie, J. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin Books.
  232. Park, S. (2014). Cultural relativism and the theory of relativity. Filosofija. Sociologija, 25(1), 44-51.
  233. Schick, T. and L. Vaughn (2010). Doing philosophy: An introduction through thought experiments. 4th ed. California: Mayfield Publishing Company.
  234. Rachels, J. and Rachels, S. (2010). The elements of moral philosophy. New York: McGraw- Hill Humanities.
  235. Rønnow-Rasmussen, T. (2017). On locating value in making moral progress. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 20(1), 137-152.
  236. Rusch, H. (2014). The evolutionary interplay of intergroup conflict and altruism in humans: A review of parochial altruism theory and prospects for its extension, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 281(1794), 1-9.
  237. Salmon, W. (1978). Why ask, "Why?"? An inquiry concerning scientific explanation. In J. Kourany (Ed.), Scientific knowledge: Basic issues in the philosophy of science. CA: Wadsworth Publishing Company.
  238. Stevenson, C. (1944). Ethics and language. New Haven: Yale University Press.
  239. Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109-166.
  240. van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press. References
  241. Bird, A. (2007). What is scientific progress? Noûs, 41(1), 92-117.
  242. Blackburn, S. (1993). Essays in quasi-realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
  243. Dellsén, F. (2016). Scientific progress: Knowledge vs. understanding. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 56, 72-83.
  244. Dellsén, F. (2022). Thinking about progress: From science to philosophy. Noûs, 56(4), 814- 840. Hare, R. (1952). Language of morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  245. Kuhn, T. (1962/1970). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  246. Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. Berkeley: University of California Press.
  247. Laudan, L. (1984). Science and values. Berkeley: University of California Press.
  248. Mackie, J. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin Books.
  249. Niiniluoto, I. (1984). Is science progressive? Dordrecht: Reidel.
  250. Niiniluoto, I. (2014). Scientific progress as increasing verisimilitude. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 46, 73-77.
  251. Park, S. (2022). Embracing scientific realism. Cham: Springer.
  252. Pojman, L. (2008). Who's to judge what's right or wrong? In S. Satris (Ed.), Taking sides: Clashing views on moral issues (pp. 13-21). Dubuque, Iowa: McGraw-Hill Companies.
  253. Rønnow-Rasmussen, T. (2017). On locating value in making moral progress. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 20(1), 137-152.
  254. Rowbottom, D. (2023). Scientific progress. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  255. Stevenson, C. (1944). Ethics and language. New Haven: Yale University Press.
  256. Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109-166. Chapter 15 The Evolutionary Debunking Argument for Moral Skepticism References
  257. Balaguer, M. (2018). Fictionalism in the philosophy of mathematics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/fictionalism-mathematics/>.
  258. Blackburn, S. (1993). Essays in quasi-realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
  259. De Cruz, H., Boudry, M., De Smedt, J., Blancke, S. (2011). Evolutionary Approaches to Epistemic Justification. Dialectica, 65(4), 517-535.
  260. De Cruz, H. and De Smedt, J. (2012). Evolved cognitive biases and the epistemic status of scientific beliefs. Philosophical Studies, 157(3), 411-429.
  261. Goldman, A. and Beddor, B. (2021). Reliabilist epistemology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/reliabilism/>.
  262. Hare, R. (1952). Language of morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  263. Mackie, J. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin Books.
  264. Moore, G. (1993). Moore's paradox. In T. Baldwin (Ed.), G.E. Moore: Selected writings (pp. 207-212). London: Routledge.
  265. Park, S. (2012). Against moral truths. Cultura: International Journal of Philosophy of Culture and Axiology, 9(1), 179-194.
  266. Park, S. (2017). In defense of mathematical inferentialism. Analysis and Metaphysics, 16: 70- 83.
  267. Park, S. (2019). Should scientists embrace scientific realism or antirealism? Philosophical Forum, 50(1), 147-158.
  268. Park, S. (2020). Replies to Healey's comments regarding van Fraassen's positions. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective, 9(1), 38-47.
  269. Rachels, J. and Rachels, S. (2010). The elements of moral philosophy. OH: McGraw-Hill Humanities. References
  270. Blackburn, S. (1993). Essays in quasi-realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
  271. Cullison, A. (2010). Moral perception. European Journal of Philosophy, 18(2), 159-175.
  272. de Ray, C. (2022). A new epistemological case for theism. Religious Studies, 58(2), 379-400.
  273. Hare, R. (1952). Language of morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  274. Hume, D. (1978). A treatise of human nature. In L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch (Eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  275. Hume, D. (1993). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
  276. Mackie, J. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin Books.
  277. Park, S. (2015). Explanatory failures of relative realism. Epistemologia, 38(1), 16-28.
  278. Park, S. (2019). The disastrous implications of the 'English' view of rationality in a social world. Social Epistemology, 33(1), 88-99.
  279. Stevenson, C. (1944). Ethics and language. New Haven: Yale University Press.
  280. Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109-166.
  281. van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.