Induction Science and Morality
2025, Springer
Abstract
I attempt to refute Hume's problem of induction. I raise the problem of counter-induction. I develop a template for generating philosophical problems. I develop and defend stage theory of scientific development for scientific realism. I develop and defend two new metaethical theories: cultural emotivism and moral functionalism. I argue that to compare morality to mathematics is to lose credibility. I develop the problem of moral induction against moral realism.
References (281)
- de Ray, C. (2022). A new epistemological case for theism. Religious Studies, 58(2), 379-400.
- Goldman, A. and Beddor, B. (2021). Reliabilist epistemology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/reliabilism/>.
- Hume, D. (1993). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
- Lee, B. (2022). A coherentist justification of induction. Erkenntnis, 87(1), 35-52.
- Norton, J. (2003). A material theory of induction. Philosophy of Science, 70(4), 647-670.
- Park, S. (2015). Explanatory failures of relative realism. Epistemologia, 38(1), 16-28.
- Park, S. (2017). The uniformity principle vs. the disuniformity principle. Acta Analytica, 32(2), 213-222.
- Park, S. (2018). The anti-induction for scientific realism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 95(3), References
- Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- de Ray, C. (2022a). A new epistemological case for theism. Religious Studies, 58(2), 379-400.
- Fine, A. (1991). Piecemeal realism. Philosophical Studies, 61(1-2), 79-96.
- Goldman, A. (1979). What is justified belief? In G. S. Pappas (Ed.), Justification and knowledge: New studies in epistemology (pp. 1-23). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
- Goldman, A. and Beddor, B. (2021). Reliabilist epistemology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/reliabilism/>.
- Hume, D. (1993). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
- Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48(1), 19-49.
- Laudan, L. (1984). Explaining the success of science: Beyond epistemic realism and relativism.
- In J. Cushing, C. Delaney, and G. Gutting (Eds.), Science and reality (pp. 83-105). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
- Lee, B. (2022). A coherentist justification of induction. Erkenntnis, 87(1), 35-52.
- Lehrer, K., (2000). Theory of knowledge, Boulder: Westview Press.
- Mizrahi, M. (2013). The argument from underconsideration and relative realism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 27(4), 393-407.
- Park, S. (2015). Explanatory failures of relative realism. Epistemologia, 38(1), 16-28.
- Park, S. (2017). The uniformity principle vs. the disuniformity principle. Acta Analytica, 32(2), 213-222.
- Park, S. (2018). The anti-induction for scientific realism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 95(3), 329-342.
- Park, S. (2023). Inference to the best explanation, naturalism, and theism. Implicit Religion, 472-485.
- Park, S. (2022). Embracing scientific realism. Cham: Springer.
- Sellars, W. (1963). Science, perception and reality. Atascadero: Ridgeview.
- Sellars, W. (1979). Essays in philosophy and its history. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.
- van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Weintraub, R. (2013). Induction and inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Studies, 166(1), 203-216.
- Wray, B. (2008). The argument from underconsideration as grounds for anti-realism: A defence. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 22(3), 317-326.
- Hume, D. (1993). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
- Norton, J. (2003). A material theory of induction. Philosophy of Science, 70(4), 647-670.
- Park, S. (2017). The uniformity principle vs. the disuniformity Principle. Acta Analytica, 32(2), 213-222.
- Park, S. (2018). The anti-induction for scientific realism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 95(3), 329-342.
- Park, S. (2022). Embracing scientific realism. Cham: Springer.
- Salmon, W. (1957). Should we attempt to justify induction? Philosophical Studies, 8(3), 33- 48. References
- Alai, M. (2017). Resisting the historical objections to realism: Is Doppelt's a viable solution? Synthese, 194(9), 3267-3290.
- de Ray, C. (2022). A new epistemological case for theism. Religious Studies, 58(2), 379-400.
- Fahrbach, L. (2011a). How the growth of science ends theory change. Synthese, 180(2), 139- 155.
- Fahrbach, L. (2011b). Theory change and degrees of success. Philosophy of Science, 78(5), 1283-1292.
- Hempel, C. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
- Mizrahi, M. (2013). The pessimistic induction: A bad argument gone too far. Synthese, 190(15), 3209-3226.
- Mizrahi, M. (2020). The relativity of theory: Key positions and arguments in the contemporary scientific realism/antirealism debate. Cham: Springer.
- Müller, F. (2015). The pessimistic meta-induction: Obsolete through scientific progress? International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 29(4), 393-412.
- Park, S. (2011). A confutation of the pessimistic induction. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 42(1), 75-84.
- Park, S. (2017). Scientific antirealists have set fire to their own houses. Prolegomena, 16(1), 23-37.
- Park, S. (2019). The disastrous implications of the 'English' view of rationality in a social world. Social Epistemology, 33(1), 88-99.
- Park, S. (2023). Inference to the best explanation, naturalism, and theism. Implicit Religion, 472-485.
- Psillos, S. (2018). Realism and theory change in science. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. In E. N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/realism-theory-change/>.
- van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Weintraub, R. (2013). Induction and inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Studies, 166(1), 203-216.
- Wray, K. (2021). Induction, rationality, and the realism/antirealism debate: A reply to Shech. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science. 34(4), 243-247.
- de Ray, C. (2022). A new epistemological case for theism. Religious Studies, 58(2), 379-400.
- Hume, D. (1993). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
- Lehrer, K., (2000). Theory of knowledge, Boulder: Westview Press.
- Park, S. (2017). The uniformity principle vs. the disuniformity principle. Acta Analytica, 32(2), 213-222.
- Park, S. (2018). The anti-induction for scientific realism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 95(3), 329-342.
- Park, S. (2021). On the argument from double spaces: A Reply to Moti Mizrahi. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective, 10(2), 1-6.
- Park, S. (2022). Embracing scientific realism. Cham: Springer.
- van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Weintraub, R. (2013). Induction and inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Studies, 166(1), 203-216.
- Hume, D. (1993). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
- Ladyman, J., Douven, I., Horsten, L., and van Fraassen, B. (1997). A defense of van Fraassen's critique of abductive inference: Reply to Psillos. The Philosophical Quarterly, 47(188), 305- 321.
- Magnus, P.D. and Callender, C. (2004). Realist ennui and the base rate fallacy. Philosophy of Science, 71(3). 320-338.
- Norton, J. (2003). A material theory of induction. Philosophy of Science, 70(4), 647-670.
- Park, S. (2017). Understanding without justification and belief? Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology, 21(3), 379-389.
- Park, S. (2022a). Embracing scientific realism. Cham: Springer.
- Park, S. (2022b). The contextual theory of explanation and inference to the best explanation. Axiomathes, 32(S2), 311-326.
- Shech, E. (2021). Darwinian-selectionist explanation, radical theory change, and the observable-unobservable dichotomy. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 34(4), 221-241.
- van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- van Fraassen, B. C. (2007). From a view of science to a new empiricism. In B. Monton (Ed.), Images of empiricism: Essays on science and stances, with a reply from Bas C. van Fraassen, (pp. 337-383). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- van Fraassen, B. (2017). Misdirection and misconception in the scientific realism debates. In E. Agazzi (Ed.), Varieties of scientific realism: Objectivity and truth in science (pp. 95-108). Cham: Springer.
- Wray, B. (2012). Epistemic privilege and the success of science. Noûs, 46(3), 375-385.
- Wray, K. (2018). Resisting scientific realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Wray, K. (2021). Induction, rationality, and the realism/antirealism debate: A reply to Shech. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 34(4), 243-247. References
- Alai, M. (2017). Resisting the historical objections to realism: Is Doppelt's a viable solution? Synthese, 194(9), 3267-3290.
- Alvaro, Carlo (2021). Atheism as an extreme rejection of rational evidence for the existence of God. The Heythrop Journal, 62(2), 1-16.
- Chakravartty, A. (2008). What you don't know can't hurt you: Realism and the unconceived. Philosophical Studies, 137(1), 149-158.
- Chang, H. (2011). The persistence of epistemic objects through scientific change. Erkenntnis, 75(3), 413-429.
- Frost-Arnold, G. (2011). From the pessimistic induction to semantic antirealism. Philosophy of Science, 78(5), 1131-1142.
- Frost-Arnold, G. (2019). How to be a historically motivated antirealist: The problem of misleading evidence. Philosophy of Science, 86(5), 906-917.
- Graham, D. (2013). Science before Socrates: Parmenides, Anaxagoras, and the new astronomy. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Harker, D. (2015). Creating scientific controversies: Uncertainty and bias in science and society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Harrison, P. (2015). The territories of science and religion. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
- Hempel, C. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall.
- Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. Berkeley: University of California Press.
- Leplin, J. (1997). A novel defense of scientific realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Lipton, P. (2005). The truth about science. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 360, 1259-1269.
- Mizrahi, M. (2016). The history of science as a graveyard of theories: A philosophers' myth. International Studies in Philosophy of Science, 30(3), 263-278.
- Müller, F. (2015). The pessimistic meta-induction: Obsolete through scientific progress? International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 29(4), 393-412.
- Musgrave, A. (1985). Realism vs. constructive empiricism. In P. Churchland & C. Hooker (Eds.), Images of science: Essays on realism and empiricism. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
- Park, S. (2016). Refutations of the two pessimistic inductions. Philosophia, 44(3), 835-844.
- Park, S. (2017). The uniformity principle vs. the disuniformity principle. Acta Analytica, 32(2), 213-222.
- Park, S. (2018a). The anti-induction for scientific realism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 95(3), 329-342.
- Park, S. (2018b). The grand pessimistic induction. Review of Contemporary Philosophy, 17, 7-19.
- Park, S. (2019a). The absolute and relative pessimistic inductions. Problemos, 95: 94-104.
- Park, S. (2019b). How to formulate scientific realism and antirealism. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 50(4), 477-488.
- Park, S. (2022). Embracing scientific realism. Cham: Springer.
- Ruhmkorff, S. (2011). "Some Difficulties for the Problem of Unconceived Alternatives", Philosophy of Science 78 (5): 875-886.
- Ruhmkorff, S. (2013). Global and local pessimistic meta-inductions. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 27(4), 409-428.
- Sorensen, R. (2013). Veridical idealizations. In M. Frappier, L. Meynell, and J. Brown, (Eds.), Thought experiments in philosophy, science, and the arts. (pp. 30-52). New York: Routledge.
- Stanford, K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Stengers, I. (2000). The invention of modern science. D. Smith (Trans.), Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
- van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- van Fraassen, B. (2007). Reply: From a view of science to a new empiricism. In B. Monton (Ed.), Images of empiricism: Essays on science and stances, with a reply from Bas van Fraassen (pp. 337-383). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- van Fraassen, B. (2017). Misdirection and misconception in the scientific realism debates. In E. Agazzi (Ed.), Varieties of scientific realism: Objectivity and truth in science (pp. 95-108). Cham: Springer.
- Bird, A. (2007). What is scientific progress? Noûs 41(1), 64-89.
- Bird, A. (2018). Thomas Kuhn. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/thomas-kuhn/>.
- Boyd, R. (1980). Scientific realism and naturalistic epistemology. PSA Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association, 1980(2), 613-662.
- Fahrbach, L. (2011a). How the growth of science ends theory change. Synthese, 180(2), 139- 155.
- Fahrbach, L. (2011b). Theory change and degrees of success. Philosophy of Science, 78(5), 1283-1292.
- Frost-Arnold, G. (2019). How to be a historically motivated antirealist: The problem of misleading evidence. Philosophy of Science, 86(5), 906-917.
- Kuhn, T. (1962/1970). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
- Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. Berkeley: University of California Press.
- Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48(1), 19-49.
- Leplin, J. (1997). A novel defense of scientific realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Lyons, T. (2005). Toward a purely axiological scientific realism. Erkenntnis, 63(2), 167-204.
- Mizrahi, M. (2013). The pessimistic induction: A bad argument gone too far. Synthese, 190(15), 3209-3226.
- Mizrahi, M. (2015). Historical inductions: New cherries, same old cherry-picking, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2), 129-148.
- Mizrahi, M. (2016). The history of science as a graveyard of theories: A philosophers' myth. International Studies in Philosophy of Science, 30(3), 263-278.
- Musgrave, A. (1985). Realism vs. constructive empiricism. In P. Churchland & C. Hooker (Eds.), Images of science: Essays on realism and empiricism. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
- Park, S. (2011). A confutation of the pessimistic induction. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 42(1), 75-84.
- Park, S. (2017). The uniformity principle vs. the disuniformity principle. Acta Analytica, 32(2), 213-222.
- Park, S. (2018a). The grand pessimistic induction. Review of Contemporary Philosophy, 17: 7-19.
- Park, S. (2018b). The anti-induction for scientific realism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 95(3), 329-342.
- Park, S. (2019). New objections to the problem of unconceived alternatives. Filosofia Unisinos, 20(2), 138-145.
- Poincaré, H. (1905/1952). Science and hypothesis. New York: Dover.
- Stanford, K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- van Fraassen, Bas (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press. References
- Akins, K. (1996). Of sensory systems and the 'aboutness' of mental states. Journal of Philosophy, 93(3), 337-372.
- Darwin, C., & Darwin, F. (1888). The life and letters of Charles Darwin. London: John Murray.
- De Cruz, H., Boudry, M., De Smedt, J., Blancke, S. (2011). Evolutionary Approaches to Epistemic Justification. Dialectica, 65(4), 517-535.
- de Ray, C. (2022). An evolutionary skeptical challenge to scientific realism. Erkenntnis, 87(2), 969-989.
- Friedman, M. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. The Journal of Philosophy, 71: 5-19.
- Goldman, A. and Beddor, B. (2021). Reliabilist epistemology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/reliabilism/>.
- Hempel, C. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
- Kuhn, T. (1962/1970). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
- Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. California: University of California Press.
- Lipton, P. (2003). Inference to the best explanation. London: Routledge.
- Park, S. (2017). Problems with using evolutionary theory in philosophy. Axiomathes, 27(3), 321-332.
- Park, S. (2022). The realist and selectionist explanations for the success of science. Synthese, 200(233). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03703-0
- Putnam, H. (1975). Mathematics, matter and method: Philosophical papers, volume 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Salmon, W. (1978). Why ask, "Why?"? An inquiry concerning scientific explanation. In J. Kourany (Ed.), Scientific knowledge: Basic issues in the philosophy of science. CA: Wadsworth Publishing Company.
- Stanford, K. (2006). Exceeding our Grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109-166.
- Alai, M. (2017). Resisting the historical objections to realism: Is Doppelt's a viable solution? Synthese, 194(9), 3267-3290.
- Alvaro, C. (2020). The incoherence of moral relativism. Cultura: International Journal of Philosophy of Culture and Axiology, 17(1), 19-38.
- Baker, A. (2005). Are there genuine mathematical explanations of physical phenomena? Mind, 114(454), 223-237.
- Blackburn, S. (1993). Essays in quasi-realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Fine, A. (1991). Piecemeal realism. Philosophical Studies, 61(1-2), 79-96.
- Hare, R. (1952). Language of morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Harman, G. (1996). Moral relativism. In S. Satris (Ed.) (2008). Taking sides: Clashing views on moral issues. 11th ed. Mcgraw-Hill/Dushkin.
- Hume, D. (1978). A treatise of human nature. In L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch (Eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science: Science without legend, objectivity without illusions. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. California: University of California Press.
- Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48(1), 19-49.
- Leplin, J. (1997). A novel defense of scientific realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Mackie, J. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin Books.
- Mizrahi, M. (2013). The pessimistic induction: A bad argument gone too far. Synthese, 190(15), 3209-3226.
- Mizrahi, M. (2015). Historical inductions: New cherries, same old cherry-picking. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 29(2), 129-148.
- Mizrahi, M. (2016). The history of science as a graveyard of theories: A philosophers' myth. International Studies in Philosophy of Science, 30(3), 263-278.
- Mizrahi, M. (2020). The relativity of theory: Key positions and arguments in the contemporary scientific realism/antirealism debate. Cham: Springer.
- Musgrave, A. (1985). Realism vs. constructive empiricism. In P. Churchland and C. Hooker (Eds.), Images of science: Essays on realism and empiricism (pp. 197-221). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
- Musgrave, A. (1988). The ultimate argument for scientific realism. In R. Nola (Ed.), Relativism and realism in science (pp. 229-252). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
- Park, S. (2009). Philosophical responses to underdetermination in science. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 40(1), 115-124.
- Park, S. (2011a). Coherence of our best scientific theories. Foundations of Science, 16(1), 21- 30.
- Park, S. (2011b). Defence of cultural relativism. Cultura. International Journal of Philosophy of Culture and Axiology, 8(1), 159-170.
- Park, S. (2011c). A confutation of the pessimistic induction. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 42(1), 75-84.
- Park, S. (2012). Against moral truths. Cultura: International Journal of Philosophy of Culture and Axiology, 9(1), 179-194.
- Park, S. (2014). A pessimistic induction against scientific antirealism. Organon F, 21(1), 3-21.
- Park, S. (2017). Moral vegetarianism vs. moral omnivorism. Human Affairs, 27(3), 289-300.
- Park, S. (2018). The anti-induction for scientific realism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 95(3), 329-342.
- Park, S. (2019). The coherence of evolutionary theory with its neighboring theories. Acta Biotheoretica, 67(2), 87-102.
- Park, S. (2022a). Embracing scientific realism. Cham: Springer.
- Park, S. (2022b). Moral subjectivism vs. moral objectivism. Filosofija. Sociologija, 33(3), 269-276.
- Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. New York: Routledge.
- Putnam, H. (1975). Mathematics, matter and method: Philosophical papers, volume 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Putnam, H. (1979). Mathematics, matter and method: Philosophical papers, volume 1. 2 nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Quine, W. (1980). From a logical point of view. 2 nd ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
- Saatsi, J. (2009). Grasping at realist straws. Metascience, 18(3), 355-362.
- Singer, P. (2009). Animal liberation: The definitive classic of the animal movement. New York: HarperCollins Publisher.
- Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.
- Stanford, K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Stevenson, C. (1944). Ethics and language. New Haven: Yale University Press.
- Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109-166.
- van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Wray, B. (2013). Pessimistic induction and the exponential growth of science reassessed. Synthese, 190(18), 4321-4330.
- Williams, E. (2015). The possibility of an ongoing moral catastrophe. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 18(5), 971-982.
- Blackburn, S. (1993). Essays in quasi-realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Bourget, D. and Chalmers, D. (2014). What do philosophers believe? Philosophical Studies, 170(3), 465-500.
- Estes, W. (1986). Array models for category learning. Cognitive Psychology, 18(4), 500-549.
- Goldman, A. (1993). The psychology of folk psychology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 16(1), 15-28.
- Goldman, A. and Beddor, B. (2021). Reliabilist epistemology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/reliabilism/>.
- Hare, R. (1952). Language of morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Huemer, M. (2016). A liberal realist answer to debunking skeptics: the empirical case for realism. Philosophical Studies, 173(7), 1983-2010.
- Mackie, J. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin Books.
- Maxwell, G. (1962). The ontological status of theoretical entities. In H. Feigl and G. Maxwell (Eds.), Scientific explanation, space, and time: Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (pp. 181-192). Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press.
- Park, S. (2012). Against moral truths. Cultura: International Journal of Philosophy of Culture and Axiology, 9(1), 179-194.
- Schick, T. Jr. and Vaughn, L. (2010). Doing philosophy: An introduction through thought experiments. New York, NY: The McGraw-Hill Companies.
- Stevenson, C. (1944). Ethics and language. New Haven: Yale University Press.
- Stich, S. (1993). Moral philosophy and mental representation. In M. Hechter, L. Nadel, and R. Michod (Eds.), The origin of values (215-228). Hawthorne, New York: Walter de Gruyter.
- Stich, S. (2019). The quest for the boundaries of morality. In A. Zimmerman, K. Jones and M. Timmons (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of moral epistemology (15-37). New York: Routledge.
- Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109-166.
- Baker, A. (2005). Are there genuine mathematical explanations of physical phenomena? Mind, 114(454), 223-237.
- Baker, A. (2009). Mathematical explanation in science. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60(3), 611-633.
- Balaguer, M. (2018). Fictionalism in the philosophy of mathematics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/fictionalism-mathematics/>.
- Bourget, D. and Chalmers, D. (2014). What do philosophers believe? Philosophical Studies, 170(3), 465-500.
- DeLapp, K. (2023). Metaethics. The Internet encyclopedia of philosophy. https://iep.utm.edu/metaethi/
- Estes, W. (1986). Array models for category learning. Cognitive Psychology, 18(4), 500-549.
- Huemer, M. (2016). A liberal realist answer to debunking skeptics: the empirical case for realism. Philosophical Studies, 173(7), 1983-2010.
- Jones, T. (1970). The classical mind: A history of Western philosophy. Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich College Publishers.
- Hume, D. (1978). A treatise of human nature. In L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch (Eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Kim, S. (2023). Moral realism. The internet encyclopedia of philosophy. https://iep.utm.edu/moralrea/
- Mackie, J. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin Books.
- Park, S. (2003). Ontological order in scientific explanation. Philosophical Papers, 32(2), 157- 170.
- Park, S. (2017). In defense of mathematical inferentialism. Analysis and Metaphysics, 16, 70- 83. Park, S. (2022a). Embracing scientific realism. Cham: Springer.
- Park, S. (2022b). Moral subjectivism vs. moral objectivism. Filosofija. Sociologija, 33, 191- 198. Putnam, H. (1971). Philosophy of logic. New York: Harper and Row.
- Quine, W. (1948). On what there is. Review of Metaphysics, 2(5), 21-38.
- Baker, A. (2005). Are there genuine mathematical explanations of physical phenomena? Mind, 114(454), 223-237.
- Baker, A. (2009). Mathematical explanation in science. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60(3), 611-633.
- Blackburn, S. (1993). Essays in quasi-realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Chagnon, N. (1988). Life histories, blood revenge, and warfare in a tribal population. Science, 239(4843), 985-992.
- Friedman, M. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. The Journal of Philosophy, 71: 5-19.
- Hare, R. (1952). Language of morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Hempel, C. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
- Huemer, M. (2016). A liberal realist answer to debunking skeptics: the empirical case for realism. Philosophical Studies, 173(7), 1983-2010.
- Kitcher, P. (1981). Explanatory unification. Philosophy of Science, 48(4), 507-531.
- Mackie, J. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin Books.
- Park, S. (2014). Cultural relativism and the theory of relativity. Filosofija. Sociologija, 25(1), 44-51.
- Schick, T. and L. Vaughn (2010). Doing philosophy: An introduction through thought experiments. 4th ed. California: Mayfield Publishing Company.
- Rachels, J. and Rachels, S. (2010). The elements of moral philosophy. New York: McGraw- Hill Humanities.
- Rønnow-Rasmussen, T. (2017). On locating value in making moral progress. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 20(1), 137-152.
- Rusch, H. (2014). The evolutionary interplay of intergroup conflict and altruism in humans: A review of parochial altruism theory and prospects for its extension, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 281(1794), 1-9.
- Salmon, W. (1978). Why ask, "Why?"? An inquiry concerning scientific explanation. In J. Kourany (Ed.), Scientific knowledge: Basic issues in the philosophy of science. CA: Wadsworth Publishing Company.
- Stevenson, C. (1944). Ethics and language. New Haven: Yale University Press.
- Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109-166.
- van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press. References
- Bird, A. (2007). What is scientific progress? Noûs, 41(1), 92-117.
- Blackburn, S. (1993). Essays in quasi-realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Dellsén, F. (2016). Scientific progress: Knowledge vs. understanding. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 56, 72-83.
- Dellsén, F. (2022). Thinking about progress: From science to philosophy. Noûs, 56(4), 814- 840. Hare, R. (1952). Language of morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Kuhn, T. (1962/1970). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
- Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. Berkeley: University of California Press.
- Laudan, L. (1984). Science and values. Berkeley: University of California Press.
- Mackie, J. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin Books.
- Niiniluoto, I. (1984). Is science progressive? Dordrecht: Reidel.
- Niiniluoto, I. (2014). Scientific progress as increasing verisimilitude. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 46, 73-77.
- Park, S. (2022). Embracing scientific realism. Cham: Springer.
- Pojman, L. (2008). Who's to judge what's right or wrong? In S. Satris (Ed.), Taking sides: Clashing views on moral issues (pp. 13-21). Dubuque, Iowa: McGraw-Hill Companies.
- Rønnow-Rasmussen, T. (2017). On locating value in making moral progress. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 20(1), 137-152.
- Rowbottom, D. (2023). Scientific progress. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Stevenson, C. (1944). Ethics and language. New Haven: Yale University Press.
- Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109-166. Chapter 15 The Evolutionary Debunking Argument for Moral Skepticism References
- Balaguer, M. (2018). Fictionalism in the philosophy of mathematics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/fictionalism-mathematics/>.
- Blackburn, S. (1993). Essays in quasi-realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
- De Cruz, H., Boudry, M., De Smedt, J., Blancke, S. (2011). Evolutionary Approaches to Epistemic Justification. Dialectica, 65(4), 517-535.
- De Cruz, H. and De Smedt, J. (2012). Evolved cognitive biases and the epistemic status of scientific beliefs. Philosophical Studies, 157(3), 411-429.
- Goldman, A. and Beddor, B. (2021). Reliabilist epistemology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/reliabilism/>.
- Hare, R. (1952). Language of morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Mackie, J. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin Books.
- Moore, G. (1993). Moore's paradox. In T. Baldwin (Ed.), G.E. Moore: Selected writings (pp. 207-212). London: Routledge.
- Park, S. (2012). Against moral truths. Cultura: International Journal of Philosophy of Culture and Axiology, 9(1), 179-194.
- Park, S. (2017). In defense of mathematical inferentialism. Analysis and Metaphysics, 16: 70- 83.
- Park, S. (2019). Should scientists embrace scientific realism or antirealism? Philosophical Forum, 50(1), 147-158.
- Park, S. (2020). Replies to Healey's comments regarding van Fraassen's positions. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective, 9(1), 38-47.
- Rachels, J. and Rachels, S. (2010). The elements of moral philosophy. OH: McGraw-Hill Humanities. References
- Blackburn, S. (1993). Essays in quasi-realism. New York: Oxford University Press.
- Cullison, A. (2010). Moral perception. European Journal of Philosophy, 18(2), 159-175.
- de Ray, C. (2022). A new epistemological case for theism. Religious Studies, 58(2), 379-400.
- Hare, R. (1952). Language of morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- Hume, D. (1978). A treatise of human nature. In L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch (Eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Hume, D. (1993). An enquiry concerning human understanding. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
- Mackie, J. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin Books.
- Park, S. (2015). Explanatory failures of relative realism. Epistemologia, 38(1), 16-28.
- Park, S. (2019). The disastrous implications of the 'English' view of rationality in a social world. Social Epistemology, 33(1), 88-99.
- Stevenson, C. (1944). Ethics and language. New Haven: Yale University Press.
- Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 109-166.
- van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.