Physical Emergence and Process Ontology
2012, Process Studies
https://doi.org/10.1080/02604020701845616Abstract
Alfred North Whitehead introduces in Process and Reality the notion that the “philosophy of organism is a cell-theory of actuality.” I argue here that the most promising venue for a concordance with process ontology vis-`a-vis extant physical theory includes the notions of dynamical and ontological emergence in the physical sciences, as described in Silberstein and McGeever (1999) as well as in Kronz and Tiehen (2002). Here I draw on my previous claims (1997, 2005, 2006) to show in more general terms how process ontology provides a more unified characterization of ontological and dynamical emergence.
References (58)
- Recall note 14. In classical mechanics, Hamiltonians also describe the energy of a system, but are defined not as operators in a vector space, but rather as functions in phase space coordinates (i.e., in terms of the position(s) and momenta of the system's constituents).
- He argues, for instance, in the case of deriving the specific heat for a classical crystal through its Hamiltonian and other purely dynamic considerations, that the "diachronic seems the more important case" (p. 120).
- Recall note 13. Again, the reader may skip the technical details of this example without loss of the conceptual points being made here. For convenience, I am adopting the Dirac notation for the spin state vectors.
- The last line in (1) adopts the shorthand representation for denoting the ordering of base elements in the composite system.
- For details demonstrating the non-factorizibility, see Kallfelz (2002, pp. 31-32).
- "The Born-Oppenheimer 'approximation' . . . is not simply a mathematical expansion in series form. . . . It literally replaces the basic quantum mechanical descriptions with a new description, generated in the limit ε →0, [for the governing parameter ε = (m e /m N ) 1/4 where m e is the mass of the orbital electron, and m N the mass of the nucleon, i.e. one forms an asymptotic series S(ε) = k a k ε k .] This replacement corresponds to a change in the algebra of observables needed for the description of molecular phenomena. . . . The Born-Oppenheimer approach amounts to a change in topology-i.e., a change in the mathematical elements modeling physical phenomena- as well as a change in ontology-including fundamental physical elements absent from quantum mechanics" (Robert Bishop, 2004, p. 4).
- As discussed in detail by Krontz and Tiehen, pp. 339-341.
- In homage to W. V. O. Quine's pragmatic holism.
- "The superseding theory T , though 'deeply containing T ' (in some non-reductive sense) cannot adequately account for emergent and critical phenomena alone, and thus enlists T in some essential manner" (Kallfelz, 2006, p. 3).
- For highly accessible overview of Clifford algebra, see Lasenby et al. (2000).
- I precisely define a "methodologically fundamental" procedure in Kallfelz (2006), pp. 11-12. Briefly, if a theory T is methodologically fundamental, then its underlying mathematical formalism, suitably characterized by any multilinear algebra, would exhibit: (a) A simple relativity group (i.e., the group describing all its covariant symmetries would not contain any invariant subgroups), (b) A stable Lie algebra (i.e., the algebra describing the class of all the infinitesimal transformations in the theory varies smoothly, or "contracts" smoothly, in the zero limit of any one of its structure constants. I borrow these notions from Segal (1951), Inonu and Wigner (1952), and Finkelstein (2001, 2004a-c) who greatly expands on Segal, Inonu and Wigner's original work.
- The space-time structure must be supplied by classical structures, prior to the definition of the dynamical algebra (Finkelstein et al., 2001, p. 5).
- That is, the simplest statistics supporting a 2-valued representation of S N , the symmetry group on N objects.
- Ayer, A. J. 1956/1998. What is a law of nature? Revue Internationale de Philosophie 36: 144-165. (Reprinted in Philosophy of science: The central issues, Eds. Curd M., and Cover J. A., 1998, 808-825. New York: W. W. Norton & Co.)
- Batterman, R. 2002. The devil in the details: Asymptotic reasoning in explanation, reduction and emergence. New York: Oxford University Press.
- --. 2003a. Response to Belot's 'Whose devil? Which details?' Philosophy of Science. Philosophy of Science Archives: Physics. Available at http://philsci- archive.pitt.edu/archive/00001623/
- --. 2003b. Intertheory relations in physics. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. Avail- able at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/physics-interrelate/
- --. 2004. Critical phenomena and breaking drops. Philosophy of Science Archives: Physics. Available at http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/archive/00001622/ --. 2005. 'Fundamental Physics': Molecular dynamics versus hydrodynamics. Phi- losophy of Science Archives: Physics. Available at http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/ archive/00000582/
- Baugh, J., Finkelstein, D., Galiautdinov, A., and Shiri-Garakani, M. 2003. Transquantum dynamics. Foundations of Physics 33(9): 1267-1275.
- Bishop, R. 2004. Patching physics and chemistry together. Proceedings Philosophy of Sci- ence Association. 19th Biennial Meeting-PSA2004: PSA 2004 Contributed Papers, Austin, Texas. Available at http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/archive/00001880/
- Carrier, M., Massey, G., and Ruetsche, L., Eds. 2000. Science at century's end: Philosophi- cal questions on the progress and limits of science. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press/Universitätsverlag Konstantz.
- Cartwright, N. 1983. How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
- --. 1999. The dappled world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Clayton, P. D. 2004. Emergence: Us from it. In Science and ultimate reality: Quantum theory, cosmology, and complexity. Eds. Barrow, J. D., Davies, P., and Harper, C., 577-606. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Earman, J., Glymour, C., and Mitchell, S. 2002. Ceteris paribus laws. Kluwer: Dordrecht.
- Eastman, T. 1997. Process thought and natural science. Process Studies (Special focus introduction on process thought and natural science, Ed. Timothy Eastman) 26(3-4): 239-246.
- Finkelstein, D. 1996. Quantum relativity: A synthesis of the ideas of Einstein and Heisen- berg. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
- Finkelstein, D., and Kallfelz, W. 1997. Organism and physics. Process Studies (Special focus introduction on Process thought and natural science, Ed. Timothy Eastman) 26(3-4): 279-292.
- Finkelstein, D., Baugh, J., Galiautdinov, A., and Saller, H. 2001. Clifford Algebra as quantum language. Journal of Mathematical Physics 42:1489. Available at http://www.physics.gatech.edu/people/faculty/finkelstein/CliffLang2001.pdf
- Finkelstein, D. 2004a. Finite quantum relativity. Available at http://www.physics.gatech.edu /people/faculty/finkelstein/FQR02.pdf
- Finkelstein, D., Baugh, J., Saller, H., and Shiri-Garakani, M. 2004b. Quan- tum binary gravity. Available at http://www.physics.gatech.edu/people/ fac- ulty/finkelstein/QBGravity031215.pdf
- Finkelstein, D., and Shiri-Garakani, M. 2004c. Finite quantum harmonic oscillator. Avail- able at http://www.physics.gatech.edu/people/faculty/finkelstein/FHO0410082.pdf
- Frisch, M. 2005. Inconsistency, asymmetry, and non-locality: A philosophical investigation of classical electrodynamics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Goldstein, H. 1980. Classical mechanics. 2nd edition. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
- Gregerson, N. H. 2003. From complexity to life: On the emergence of life and meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Hempel, K. 1988. Provisos: A problem concerning the inferential function of scientific theories. Erkenntnis 28: 147-164. (Reprinted in The limitations of deductivism, Eds.
- Gruenbaum, A., and Salmon, W., 19-36. Berkeley: University of California Press.)
- Hestenes, D. and Sobczyk, G. 1984. Clifford algebras to geometric calculus: A unified language for mathematics and physics. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
- Hoefer, C. 2002. For fundamentalism. Philosophy of Science Archives. Available at http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/archive/00001076/
- Humphreys, P. 1996. Aspects of emergence. Philosophical Topics 24(1): 53-70.
- --. 1997. How properties emerge. Philosophy of Science 64: 1-17.
- --. 2000. Extending Ourselves. In Eds. Carrier, M., Massey, G., & Ruetsche, L., 13-33. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
- Hüttermann, A. 2005. Explanation, emergence, and quantum entanglement. Philosophy of Science 72: 114-127.
- Inonu, E., and Wigner, E. 1952. On the contraction of groups and their representations. Proceedings of the National Academy of the Sciences 39: 510-524.
- Kallfelz, W. 2002. Course notes for IDS 300 (Science and Religion), Piedmont Col- lege, Demorest, GA. URL: IDS300 link of Courses Recently Taught. Available at http://www.glue.umd.edu/∼wkallfel or directly available at http://www.wam.umd.edu /∼wkallfel/SciRelKallfelz.pdf --. 2005. Contracting Batterman's 'No-Man's Land:' Reduction rejoins expla- nation. Philosophy of Science Archives: Physics. Available at http://philsci- archive.pitt.edu/archive/00002402/
- --. 2006. Methodological fundamentalism: Why Batterman's different notions of funda- mentalism don't make a difference. Philosophy of Science Archives: Physics. Avail- able at http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/archive/00002402/
- Kauffman, S. 2000. Investigations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Kronz, F., and Tiehen, J. 2002. Emergence and quantum mechanics. Philosophy of Science 69: 324-347.
- Lasenby, J., Lasenby, A., and Doran, C. 2000. A unified mathematical language for physics and engineering in the 21st century. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of Londone A, 358: 21-39.
- Laughlin, R. L. 2005. A different universe: Reinventing physics from the bottom down. New York: Basic Books.
- Morreau, M. 1997. Fainthearted conditionals. Journal of Philosophy 94:187-211.
- --. 1999. Other things being equal. Philosophical Studies 96: 163-182.
- Morowitz, Harold. 2002. The emergence of everything: How the universe became complex. New York: Oxford University Press.
- O'Connor, T., and Hong Y. W. 2003. Emergent properties. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. Available at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/properties-emergent/
- Segal, I. E. 1951. A class of operator algebras which are determined by groups. Duke Mathematical Journal 18: 221.
- Silberstein, M., and McGeever, J. 1999. The search for ontological emergence. The Philo- sophical Quarterly 49(195): 182-200.
- Sklar, L. 2003. Dappled theories in a uniform world. Philosophy of Science 70: 424-442.
- Whitehead, A. N. 1929/1978. Process and reality (corrected edition). New York: Free Press.