Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Outline

Gauthier and the rationality of justice

1994, Philosophical Studies

https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00989717

References (15)

  1. Gauthier, Morals by Agreement, pp. 170-177.
  2. Gauthier, Morals by Agreement, pp. 178-179,226.
  3. Kraus and Coleman, "Morality and the Theory of Rational Choice," pp. 737-738.
  4. Here I am appealing to Selten's notion of a trembling-hand equilibrium. (R. Selten, "Re-examination of the Perfectness Concept for Equilibrium Points in Extensive Games," International Journal of Game Theory (1975) 4: 25-55) An equilibrium is trembling- hand perfect if it remains rational for each given a small probability that the other players may deviate from the equilibrium point. The equilibrium Narrow-Narrow-Broad is not trembling-hand perfect.
  5. s Peter Danielson, "The Visible Hand of Morality," Canadian JournalofPhilosophy 18(1988): 357-384; see pp. 376-381.
  6. 9 RNC corresponds to Danielson's SC, Selfsame Cooperation. Danielson, "The Visible Hand of Morality," pp. 378,382-383.
  7. Danielson, "The Visible Hand of Morality," pp. 382-383.
  8. 11 Thomas Schelling, The Strategy of Conflict (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1960), pp. 54-58, 83-118.
  9. See Gauthier, Morals by Agreement, pp. 194-197.
  10. Gauthier, Morals by Agreement, p. 134.
  11. David Gauthier, "Morality, Rational Choice, and Semantic Representation," Social Philosophy and Policy 5 (1987): 198-199;
  12. David Gauthier, "Moral Artifice," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18 (1988): 397.
  13. I'm assuming that society remains in a state of relative scarcity of agents: that marginal productivity always exceeds average productivity. 16 The concept of the core was developed by D. B. Gallies and Lloyd Shapley in 1953.
  14. See Martin Shubik, Game Theory in the Social Sciences (Cambridge, MA: MIT, t 982), p. 136. Department of Philosophy University of Texas at Austin Austin, TX 78712-1180
  15. USA