Gauthier and the rationality of justice
1994, Philosophical Studies
https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00989717References (15)
- Gauthier, Morals by Agreement, pp. 170-177.
- Gauthier, Morals by Agreement, pp. 178-179,226.
- Kraus and Coleman, "Morality and the Theory of Rational Choice," pp. 737-738.
- Here I am appealing to Selten's notion of a trembling-hand equilibrium. (R. Selten, "Re-examination of the Perfectness Concept for Equilibrium Points in Extensive Games," International Journal of Game Theory (1975) 4: 25-55) An equilibrium is trembling- hand perfect if it remains rational for each given a small probability that the other players may deviate from the equilibrium point. The equilibrium Narrow-Narrow-Broad is not trembling-hand perfect.
- s Peter Danielson, "The Visible Hand of Morality," Canadian JournalofPhilosophy 18(1988): 357-384; see pp. 376-381.
- 9 RNC corresponds to Danielson's SC, Selfsame Cooperation. Danielson, "The Visible Hand of Morality," pp. 378,382-383.
- Danielson, "The Visible Hand of Morality," pp. 382-383.
- 11 Thomas Schelling, The Strategy of Conflict (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1960), pp. 54-58, 83-118.
- See Gauthier, Morals by Agreement, pp. 194-197.
- Gauthier, Morals by Agreement, p. 134.
- David Gauthier, "Morality, Rational Choice, and Semantic Representation," Social Philosophy and Policy 5 (1987): 198-199;
- David Gauthier, "Moral Artifice," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18 (1988): 397.
- I'm assuming that society remains in a state of relative scarcity of agents: that marginal productivity always exceeds average productivity. 16 The concept of the core was developed by D. B. Gallies and Lloyd Shapley in 1953.
- See Martin Shubik, Game Theory in the Social Sciences (Cambridge, MA: MIT, t 982), p. 136. Department of Philosophy University of Texas at Austin Austin, TX 78712-1180
- USA