Rationalizable Strategic Behavior
1984, Econometrica
https://doi.org/10.2307/1911196…
26 pages
1 file
Sign up for access to the world's latest research
Abstract
RATIONALIZABLE STRATEGIC BEHAVIOR This paper examines the nature of rational choice in strategic games. Although there are many reasons why an agent might select a Nash equilibrium strategy in a particular game, rationality alone does not require him to do so. A natural extension of widely accepted axioms for rational choice under uncertainty to strategic environments generates an alternative class of strategies, labelled "rationalizable." It is argued that no rationalizable strategy can be discarded on the basis of rationality alone, and that all rationally justifiable strategies are members of the rationalizable set. The properties of rationalizable strategies are studied, and refinements are considered.
Related papers
Synthese, 2021
Against the orthodox view of the Nash equilibrium as “the embodiment of the idea that economic agents are rational” (Aumann, 1985, 43), some theorists have proposed ‘non-classical’ concepts of rationality in games, arguing that rational agents should be capable of improving upon inefficient equilibrium outcomes. This paper considers some implications of these proposals for economic theory, by focusing on institutional design. I argue that revisionist concepts of rationality conflict with the constraint that institutions should be designed to be incentive-compatible, that is, that they should implement social goals in equilibrium. To resolve this conflict, proponents of revisionist concepts face a choice between three options: (1.) reject incentive compatibility as a general constraint, (2.) deny that individuals interacting through the designed institutions are rational, or (3.) accept that their concepts do not cover institutional design. I critically discuss these options and I argue that a more inclusive concept of rationality, e.g. the one provided by Robert Sugden’s version of team reasoning, holds the most promise for the non-classical project, yielding a novel argument for incentive compatibility as a general constraint.
2018
This dissertation combines four studies which investigate the strategic behavior in games. The first two studies are based on experiments and develop theories of bounded rationality in order to explain the observed behavior. This behavior violates the minimal conditions of game-theoretic rationality, i.e., that equilibrium strategies must be chosen. Instead, real behavior is driven by heuristics like fairness standards and rules of thumb. Game-theoretic rationality is too strong or it is simply inadequate to explain the behavior. The two other studies are concerned with equilibrium selection. For this purpose, game-theoretic rationality is too weak to be able to single out a unique equilibrium as the rational solution of a game. A theory of unbounded rationality is applied to determine the solutions of specific games. The first study (Selten, Mitzkewitz & Uhlich, 1997) is concerned with a finite repetition of a Cournot duopoly. Experienced subjects program strategies for this game a...
The analysis of dynamic games hinges on assumptions about players' actions and beliefs at information sets that are not expected to be reached during game play. However, under the standard assumption that players are sequentially rational, these assumptions cannot be tested on the basis of observed, on-path behavior. This paper introduces a novel optimality criterion, structural rationality, which addresses this concern. In any dynamic game, structural rationality implies sequential rationality. If players are structurally rational , assumptions about on-path beliefs concerning off-path actions, as well as off-path beliefs, can be tested via suitable " side bets. " Structural rationality can also be characterized via trembles, or belief perturbations. Finally, structural rationality is consistent with experimental evidence about play in the extensive and strategic form, and justifies the use of the strategy method (Selten, 1967) in experiments.
We consider strategic-form games with ordinal payoffs and provide a syntactic analysis of common belief/knowledge of rationality, which we define axiomatically. Two axioms are considered. The first says that a player is irrational if she chooses a particular strategy while believing that another strategy is better. We show that common belief of this weak notion of rationality characterizes the iterated deletion of pure strategies that are strictly dominated by pure strategies. The second axiom says that a player is irrational if she chooses a particular strategy while believing that a different strategy is at least as good and she considers it possible that this alternative strategy is actually better than the chosen one. We show that common knowledge of this stronger notion of rationality characterizes the restriction to pure strategies of the iterated deletion procedure introduced by Stalnaker (1994). Frame characterization results are also provided.
1998
Since the publication of Herbert Simon's Sciences of the Artificial (Simon, 1981), the concept of rationality and rational action has been central to the study of Artificial Intelligence (AI) and, more recently, to the study of intelligent agents and multi-agent systems. One (of the many possible) ways of defining agents is as rational decision makers, and indeed, one recent textbook on AI defines AI itself as the enterprise of constructing such rational agents (Russell and Norvig, 1995).
Theory and Decision
This paper introduces a new solution concept for games with incomplete preferences. The concept is based on rationalizability and it is more general than the existing ones based on Nash equilibrium. In rationalizable strategies, we assume that the players choose nondominated strategies given their beliefs of what strategies the other players may choose. Our solution concept can also be used, e.g., in ordinal games where the standard notion of rationalizability cannot be applied. We show that the sets of rationalizable strategies are the maximal mutually nondominated sets. We also show that no new rationalizable strategies appear when the preferences are refined, i.e., when the information gets more precise. Moreover, noncooperative multicriteria games are suitable applications of incomplete preferences. We apply our framework to such games, where the outcomes are evaluated according to several criteria and the payoffs are vector-valued. We use the sets of feasible weights to represent the relative importance of the criteria. We demonstrate the applicability of the new solution concept with an ordinal game and a bicriteria Cournot game.
Linguistics and Philosophy, 2014
I am very grateful to Franke (2014) for giving me the opportunity of clarifying my views. I also appreciate his epistemic justification of the solution concept I employed in my article (2013). I have argued that iterated admissibility (or IA) can easily explain scalar implicatures. In order to respond to Franke's objections I need to embed that account in a larger strategy, to the effect that forward induction (FI) is the most appropriate solution concept in game-theoretic pragmatics. Forward induction first appeared in the '80s in the work of Elon Kohlberg and Jean-François Mertens. It is not a sharply defined notion, it rather embodies some intuitive principles that have been formalised in several different ways. Its intuitive significance can be expressed as the principle that, when a player observes an unexpected action on the part of some opponent, whenever this is possible, she should revise her beliefs in a way compatible with the assumption that the opponent is acting rationally. It covers several formal criteria such as the intuitive criterion (Cho and Kreps 1987), never a weak best response and stability (Kohlberg and Mertens 1986). Also IA is a possible formalisation of FI, even if it is one of the oldest solution concepts in game theory, dating back to the '50s. The connection between FI and IA hinges on the fact that a reasonable way of rationalising an opponent's action is to presume that he did not choose a dominated strategy. Like its very name suggests, IA is an iterative procedure, but so are many FI-based criteria, e.g. never a weak best response and some varieties of the intuitive criterion. According to the dominant view in game theory, the acceptable solutions must be Nash equilibria. It is well known, though, that many Nash equilibria are implausible, S. Pavan (B)
SSRN Electronic Journal
In this paper we study common belief in rationality in strategic-form games with ordinal utilities, employing a model of qualitative beliefs. We characterize the three main solution concepts for such games, viz., Iterated Deletion of Strictly Dominated Strategies (IDSDS), Iterated Deletion of Börgers-dominated Strategies (IDBS) and Iterated Deletion of Inferior Strategy Profiles (IDIP), by means of gradually restrictive properties imposed on the models of qualitative beliefs. As a corollary, we prove that IDIP refines IDBS, which refines IDSDS.
Mathematical Social Sciences, 1988
Most standard solution concepts of extensive games are history-insensitive in the sense that no matter at which information set one is, it is assumed that each player believes that everybody else is rational. In reality, each history of moves reveals certain traits of the players to one another. It is argued in this paper that solution concepts ought to make use of this fact. An example of such a concept is developed and called a 'reasonable solution' set. It is shown that this can explain cooperation in certain finitely-repeated games like the Prisoner's Dilemma.

Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.