Husserl on Meaning and Grammar
2015, Pre-proceedings of the 46th Husserl Circle Meeting, Helsinki 2015
Abstract
In the Logical Investigations Husserl sets out the idea of a Logical Grammar as a theory intended to explain how complex expressions can be constructed out of simple ones so that their meaning turns out to be determined by the meanings of their constituent parts and the way they are put together. Meanings are therefore classified into formal categories that match the syntactic categories of linguistic expressions, so that the logical properties of expressions turn out to reflect their grammatical properties. As long as linguistic meaning reduces to the intentional content of mental representations, however, it is not trivial to account for how they relate to syntax. Husserl’s take on these issues suggests the following: 1) The syntactic form of representations (both mental and linguistic) carries information about their semantic role; 2) The logical form of representations supervenes on their syntactic form; 3) The phenomenology of thought is broadly language-like.
References (22)
- Bar-Hillel. Y. (1957), "Husserl's Conception of a Purely Logical Grammar", in J.N. Mohanty (ed.), Readings on Edmund Husserl's Logical Investigations, Nijhoff, Den Haag, pp. 129- 136.
- Bundgaard, P. (2004), "The Ideal Scaffolding of Language: Husserl's Fourth Logical Investigation in the Light of Cognitive linguistics", in Phenomenology and the Cognitive Science, pp. 49-80, 2004.
- Centrone, S. (2010), "Functions in Frege, Bolzano and Husserl", in History and Philosophy of Logic, 31 (4), pp. 315-336.
- Chomsky, N. (1995), The minimalist program, MIT Press, Cambridge (MA).
- Crane, T. (2001), Elements of mind, CUP, Cambridge.
- De Boers, Th. (1978), The development of Husserl's thought, Nijhoff, Den Haag.
- Dummett, M. (1973), Frege. Philosophy of language, Duckworth, London.
- Fodor, J. (1985), "Fodor's Guide to Mental Representations" in Mind 94 (373), pp. 76-100.
- Fodor, J. (2008), LOT 2, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
- Frege, G. (1892), "Über Begriff und Gegenstand", in Vierteljahrschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie, 16, pp. 192-205, engl. translation by P. Geach "On concept and object", in Mind (60) 238, pp. 168-180.
- Hauser, M., Chomsky, N., Fitch, W. (2002), "The Faculty of language: what is it, who has it, and how did it evolve?" in Science, 298 (22):1569-1579.
- Husserl, E. (1900) Logische Untersuchungen. Erster Band: Prolegomena zur reinen Logik, Nijhoff, Den Haag 1975.
- Husserl E. (1913a) Logische Untersuchungen. Zweiter Band: Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis. Erster Teil, Nijhoff, Den Haag 1984. Husserl (1913b), Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Erstes Buch: Allgemeine Einführung in die reine Phänomenologie, a cura di K. Schumann, Nijhoff, Den Haag 1976.
- Husserl E. (1921), Logische Untersuchungen. Zweiter Band: Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis. Zweiter Teil, Nijhoff, Den Haag 1984.
- Husserl, E. (1929), Formale und transzendentale Logik. Versuch einer Kritik der logischen Vernunft, Nijhoff, Den Haag 1974.
- Husserl, E. (1939), Erfahrung und Urteil. Untersuchungen zur Genealogie der Logik, hrsg.
- L. Landgrebe, Akademia Verlagsbuchhandlung, Prag 1939, Meiner, Hamburg 1985 6 ).
- Mulligan, K. (1995), "Perception", in Smith, B., Smith D. W. (eds.), A companion to Husserl, CUP, Cambridge 1995, pp. 168-238.
- Rizzoli, L. (2002), "Bedeutung und Syntax. Ausdrucksbedeutung und Referenzgengenstand in Husserls Bedeutungstheorie", in D. Carr, C. Lotz (a cura di), Subjektivität - Verantwortung -Wahrheit. Neue Aspekte der Phänomenologie Edmund Husserls, Lang, Frankfurt am Main, pp. 163-181.
- Russell, B. (1903), Principles of mathematics, Norton, New York.
- Salmon, N. (2005), "Are general terms rigid?" in Linguistics and Philosophy 28 (1) 117-134.
- Soames (2010), What is meaning?, Princeton University Press, Princeton.